Book review: David Koepsell’s Who Owns You?: The Corporate Gold-Rush to
Patent Your Genes Randall
Mayes Science
& Technology Writer/ Policy Analyst randy.mayes@duke.edu Journal of Evolution and Technology - Vol. 20 Issue 2 – December
2009 - pgs 80-85 Who Owns You: The Corporate Gold-Rush to Patent
Your Genes. David Koepsell. Wiley-Blackwell, ISBN: 140518731X Pasteur patented a form of yeast for making beer in 1873,
and scientists received patents for hybrid plants in the early 1900s. In the
1980s, however, patents issued on drugs derived from genetically engineered human
proteins and genetically modified
bacteria intended to break down oil brought activists out of the woodwork. Bioconservatives
challenged the patents for moral reasons and liberals for economic reasons
based on their own system of values. With the more recent ability to sequence genomes and
the subsequent increase in gene patents, opposition has once again resurfaced.
This year the ACLU, representing a number of clients, is challenging the
constitutionality of patents on two breast cancer genes and the proprietary
licensing of a diagnostic test to detect the presence of these genes. In Who Owns
You?: The Corporate Gold-Rush to Patent Your Genes, David Koepsell, trained
as a lawyer and philosopher, approaches the topic of gene patents by discussing
the science of To discuss the first hot button of gene ownership and perceived
issues relating to personhood relating to patenting genes, it is first necessary
to consider the basics of patenting Koepsell's discussion should take the fight out of any
critic’s moral argument against patenting genes. Yet it is unclear why the
author chooses to repeat the concept of ownership
of genes throughout the book, as well as the title. If the reader is not
knowledgeable about patent law and misses several sentences which accurately
state that patents are not a possessory right, together with the reference to
the Thirteenth Amendment, they may actually believe patent holders own genes,
rather than owning a patent. The latter is, of course, totally different. This
is the first weakness of the book. The concept would be less confusing to the
reader had the repeated use of “owning genes” been more rigorously and
consistently qualified throughout. Koepsell is well aware of this issue, and he
concedes nobody actually owns genes. Why, then, insist on such misleading and
tendentious language? To press the second hot button in the title, corporate
greed, Koepsell credits Craig Venter as leading “The Corporate Gold-Rush to
Patent Your Genes,” and the mere mention of Venter's name is guaranteed to
rally critics of patenting genes. But in reality, a number of companies
patented genes decades earlier than Venter. In developing this theme of profit
and greed, Koepsell claims that legal errors were made by the courts in allowing
gene patents. He calls for “reasoned introspection,” since he believes the American
federal government failed to provide adequate public discussions. This argument
assumes that public input is crucial for public decision making on the legality
of gene patents. Compare the situation that arose in 1976: when
confronted by the novel and misunderstood field of genetic engineering,
scientists in the field organized the Asilomar Conference to discuss the future direction for their research. This
meeting engaged the public through education and addressed public perceptions, but
did no involve the public decision making in the highly specialized field. Today,
genetic engineering remains harmless, and Asilomar is a
successful paradigm for evaluating
the consequences of emerging technologies. In contrast, lawmakers in the However, the If you were an American taxpayer in the late 1980s and
1990s, you helped pay for the sequencing of the human genome. In 1988, James
Watson justified the hefty $3 billion price tag by convincing Congress that the
project had the potential to advance medical treatments and provide a
tremendous boost to the biotechnology and pharmaceutical industries. In Origins of the Human Genome Project, Robert
Cook-Deegan, a Science administrators and members
of Congress who shepherded the budgets for genome research (and their
counterparts in other nations and international organizations) supported the
project not only because of its medical benefits, but also because they saw it
as a vehicle for technological advance and creation of jobs and wealth. The
main policy rationale for genome research was the pursuit of gene maps as
scientific tools to conquer disease, but economic development was an explicit,
if subsidiary, goal. (Cook-Deegan 1994.) While Venter and other biotech companies
have legally patented genes, they are not alone. Educational institutions and
hospitals, and even the Koepsell rightly gives attention to the
case of Moore v. Regents of the University of California, where Notably absent from Koepsell’s book, however, is the
inconvenient truth about government
greed, notably the Clinton Administration’s actions that led to the demise of
the Human Genome Diversity Project (HGDP). In 1991, a group of scientists led by Luca Cavalli-Sforza of The Department of Commerce filed for a second patent
on a cell line from a native of the Debra Harry, an activist and member of an advocacy
group called The Indigenous Peoples Council on Biocolonialism, then called for
a boycott of the HGDP. The strong and persistent opposition that Luca
Cavalli-Sforza and his colleagues received from such groups led to the program’s
demise. A 1997 National Academy of Sciences report recommended that the
National Science Foundation and the NIH no longer fund the HGDP. By selectively choosing the facts, Koepsell presents
an unfair argument for the prevalence of corporate greed. This may persuade
readers who are unfamiliar with the full story, but it can only undermine the
book’s credibility for those who are more knowledgeable in the field. They
will, rightly, see the book as portraying an incomplete and unrealistic
picture. This is the second weakness of Who
Owns You? Koepsell uses the strategy of placing the current biotechnology
infrastructure on trial, rather than providing an example where the concept of
a genetic commons has achieved success or adequately demonstrated its economic
effectiveness. This is the third weakness in his case. Despite Koepsell’s
argument, a number of developed countries allow the private sector to patent
genes as a means to the end of increased quality of life through wealth
creation, cures for diseases, and useful products. Historically, useful products were frequently not
developed in the absence of incentives – so society could not receive the
benefits. For example, Scottish bacteriologist Alexander Fleming accidentally
discovered penicillin in 1928 after leaving a Petri dish of Staphylococcus
bacterial culture uncovered for several days and later found it covered with
mold. Fleming then discovered the mold was dissolving all the bacteria
surrounding it. However, he did not file for a patent or pursue drug
development. The antibacterial properties produced by molds in penicillin did not become commercially available until
1941, after the Scientists have an incentive not to share with others
because of the free-rider problem: other parties can benefit from an invention
although they did not share the costs of product development. When inventions
are underutilized because public goods or services are not developed, a
government failure occurs. Situations that lead to government failures require
government regulations to correct the situation. Patents provide an economic
incentive to commercialize products and ensure they are made available to the
public rather than developing trade secrets or not pursuing them. Following the Cold War, a shift to applied research
took place which led to biotech hubs that included Because of a lack of incentives to create useful
products, the Because of the interdisciplinary nature of discussions
that relate to the merits of patenting Because the topic caters to a relatively small
audience, this book is part of Wiley-Blackwell's public philosophy series, which
engages the public with discussions of topics of public importance. Does the
book succeed in this aim? The only other review of the book that I have seen is
by Chris Holman (Holman 2009), a patent attorney with a doctorate in
biochemistry and molecular biology. His review pointed out Koepsell’s errors in
patent law. In response, Koepsell dismissed Holman as unqualified to review his
book, since he did not have advanced training in metaphysics (Koepsell 2009). Surely this act is counter to the intentions of the
publisher. Unfortunately, it
appears that Koepsell will accept no one as properly qualified to review his
work unless they possess
qualifications similar to his own. Some activists, including Koepsell, remain determined
to take on the tremendous task of challenging, and ultimately overturning, the
current intellectual property infrastructure that supports the biotechnology industry. This leads me to the book's fourth
weakness: I concur with Holman that Koepsell’s arguments have what might be
called a pastiche factor, and that the book was published a decade too late. All
of the arguments presented were argued ad
nauseam by previous activists without success in influencing public policy,
and Koepsell has little to add that is genuinely new. Despite all the activists’ arguments, including
Koepsell’s, it remains unclear how preventing pharmaceutical and biotech
companies from seeking profits will speed up the search for cures to diseases. Since
the release of Koepsell’s book, advocates of the genetic commons idea have
suffered another blow. In Prometheus v.
Mayo (2009), the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Federal Circuit unanimously
reversed a district court’s ruling and consequently protected the intellectual
property of a diagnostic test for metabolites; this test is important in
personalized medicine, and the case sets an important legal precedent. While activists including Koepsell argue against gene
patenting, other scholars and activists have taken another route. They are more
solution oriented, concentrating on patent reform to overcome ineffective
government patent regulation, and on translational genomics to actually find cures
for diseases thus justifying the use of hard-earned taxpayer dollars. References Cook-Deegan, R. M. 1994.
Origins of the human genome project. Risk: Health, Safety & Environment. Vol.5. Spring. 97–118. www.piercelaw.edu/risk/vol5/spring/cookdeeg.htm Holman, C. 2009. Book review of Who Owns You? http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=17005 Koepsell, D. 2009. Why I believe gene patenting is wrong,
although it is currently legal. August 16. p. 6. http://ieet.org/index.php/IEET/more/koepsell20090816 Whelan, M. 2006. What, if any, are the ethical obligations
of the U.S. Patent Office?: A closer look at the biological sampling of indigenous
groups. Duke Law and Technology Review. iBRIEF 0014. Wilson, J. 2002. No patents for semantic information. The American Journal of Bioethics. 2(3):15-16. |