Uninsured, Heal
Thyself, Or: A New Argument for Universal Health Care Mark Walker Department of Philosophy, E-mail: mwalker@nmsu.edu Journal of Evolution and Technology - Vol. 20 Issue 2 –December 2009 - pgs 70-79 http://jetpress.org/v20/walker.htm Abstract Approximately one
in six persons in the Keywords: computer-diagnosis, insurance, justice, self-medication, universal
healthcare. 1. Introduction How does access to professional health care promote
good health? At least two answers immediately suggest themselves: (a) health
care practitioners have knowledge and expertise in the art of healing, and (b)
health care practitioners have a monopoly on writing prescriptions. These two
reasons indicate why there are obvious repercussions for those who do not have
reasonable access to physicians’ services.1 Of course, the word
“reasonable” is important here. After all, there is the old joke – for those who enjoy gallows humor – that the To support this position, I will make an argument with
two steps. The first is the following general principle: Principle
of Just Access to Medicine
(JAM): If one does not have reasonable access to a qualified physician then,
other things being equal, it is morally permissible to self-prescribe at least
some of the medicines available currently by physician prescription only. The second step is to claim that at least some persons
in the Crucial to JAM is what counts as “reasonable access.”
For instance, I imagine that there is near universal assent to applying JAM
where it is physically impossible to employ the services of a physician.
Imagine you are the last surviving member of an ill-fated scientific expedition
to a remote mountain in Of course, no one would blame you for taking the
antibiotics and breaking the law in this instance. After all, your need is
great, and you have no immediate access to a physician. Of course, you could
wait ten days for a physician, but this would be to put your health, and
possibly your life, at serious risk. It would be hard to believe that even
Socrates would recommend kowtowing to the law of your native land in this case.
Since it would be unreasonable to deny access, the principle of JAM licenses
self-medication in this instance. JAM also is relevant where one would have to put
oneself in serious jeopardy to employ the services of a physician. Suppose the
expedition’s emergency satellite phone ended up on the other side of a chasm.
The chasm is pretty wide, but you figure there is a 95% chance that you could
jump safely, and a mere 5% chance that you will fall to your death. You figure
that if you take the antibiotics, your chances of surviving until the rescue
party arrives are better than 99.9%. If you do not take the antibiotics, and do
not make the perilous jump, then you estimate your chances of survival are less
than 95%. Since it is unreasonable to insist that you take such large risks,
JAM says that it is permissible for you to take the safer course: take the
antibiotics without authorization from a physician and wait for rescue workers. Imagine now a monetary variant on our example. This
time the emergency phone is in reach. When you go to use it, however, you find
it is damaged; it will dial only one number. To your relief the number is one
that is in service; someone named “Justin” picks up. You explain your plight to
Justin and Justin agrees to call authorities for you on the condition that you
consent to sign over the deed to your house and have your wages garnished to
minimum wage level with the garnishment going to him. You say that this is a totally
exorbitant price to pay, and Justin says that he sympathizes with your plight.
It was bad luck that got you into your current straits, but Justin too had a
string of bad luck. He was laid off from his job last year and he lost his
medical insurance. Illness forced him to sell his house. He has found work
again, but it pays only a fraction of what he used to earn. So, Justin faces a
crushing debt from his medical expenses. Now, says Justin, fortune favors him
and misfortune favors you. You consider that it would be possible to comply
with his demands: you could move into a small apartment with your two children,
but it would be a huge financial burden. You could not, for example, afford
Internet if you comply with Justin’s demand, and you know how important the
Internet is for your children’s schoolwork. So, although it would be possible
to comply, still, Justin’s monetary demands are outrageous. Fortunately, JAM
authorizes you to self-medicate: you could take the antibiotics and wait to be
rescued. The cost to your well-being, and that of your family, means that you
do not have reasonable access to physicians’ services. 3.
Applying JAM The next step in the argument is to show that the
principle applies to our present political reality. Before we do this, however,
notice that JAM can be interpreted in broader and narrower terms along two
dimensions. One is the issue, which we have begun to explore, as to what
constitutes “reasonable” access? The broadest construal might mean that even
the slightest inconvenience constitutes unreasonable denial of access; the
narrowest may claim that only physical impossibility counts as unreasonable
denial of access. I will take a moderate view here, suggesting that some
sacrifices to our own and our loved ones’ well-being are too great to
constitute reasonable access. I will focus on a proper subset of the uninsured
in the The second dimension says something about the
services, pharmaceuticals, etc., that should be available for self-prescription.
The broadest construal here would be that persons ought to be able to
self-prescribe anything a physician might prescribe at any time. I will argue
for a very modest position, that routine antibiotics to treat common
infections, along with the associated lab tests, ought to be available for
self-prescription. Narrowing the range of what may be self-prescribed should
allay the objection that people will self-prescribe heroin or other drugs if
given the slightest opportunity. Also, the narrower position is more defensible
but also of significant practical importance. Antibiotics are undoubtedly the
single most important pharmaceutical innovation in the last century. Their
continued importance can be seen from the fact that upper respiratory tract
infections are the most common reason for seeking health care services in the In the Unfortunately, she has developed a sore throat and
through some online investigation she has narrowed the cause to a viral
infection, or the bacteria infection commonly referred to as “strep throat.”
Under the present system her choices are (a) do nothing or (b) see a physician
and pay out of pocket for the services ($75), and then possibly a strep test
($25) and antibiotics ($50) (alternatively, she could go to the local hospital
and be billed for the physician’s services, etc., in which case she is no
further ahead). If she were allowed to self-diagnose and self-medicate (SDM), a
third option would be available to her: (c) she could access information for
free on the Internet, pay for the strep-test out of pocket ($25) and write her
own prescription for antibiotics ($50) if necessary. The table below summarizes
the options open to Jill:
So, consulting a physician to discover she has a viral
infection will cost her four times as much as the SDM option ($100 versus $25).
Consulting a physician to find out she has strep throat, and the associated
treatment, will end up costing her twice as much as the SDM option ($150 versus
$75). We can think of this in terms of what she must sacrifice in each case. If
she has a viral infection, then on the SDM option, she will be out only $25 and
so will not have to sacrifice her son’s soccer league aspirations nor her
Internet connection. To confirm a viral infection by employing a physician will
require her to sacrifice the soccer league for her son, and still leave her
scrambling to come up with $25 or face losing her Internet access. If she has
strep throat then on the SDM option this will mean no soccer for her son, but
no loss of Internet access. Consulting a physician to confirm a strep throat
diagnosis will mean no soccer and no Internet for six months or so. In short,
she will have to pay an unreasonable cost to the well-being of her family in
order to employ the services of the physicians’ monopoly. Notice, too, that the
reasoning here overlaps with the case where you refuse to accede to Justin’s
demands that would require you to sacrifice the well-being of your family. Critics will point out that an assumption of the
argument is that the uninsured will in fact benefit from SDM. However, in fact
self-diagnosis is unreliable, which means there is a chance of misdiagnosis.
Indeed, the point may be pressed since the danger is twofold: people may
self-medicate for diseases or injuries that they do not have, and they may not
notice symptoms or make the appropriate inference as to their actual ailment.
Indeed, fuel for the objection is spurred by the fact that even trained medical
professionals are encouraged or required to seek the help of other physicians.
The usual injunction is: Physician, do not heal thyself. There are two replies to this objection, a small one
and a big one. The smaller point is that the contrast here is not between
physician infallibility and complete incompetence on the part of patients. In
either case, it is always a matter of probabilities and the difference here may
be much less than one imagines. An average visit to a physician takes about 15
minutes. Physicians can and do misdiagnose frequently: they prescribe for
nonexistent diseases or injuries and fail to notice symptoms or make the
correct inferences. An article in the Journal
of the American Medical Association noted: “Two 1998 studies validate the
continued truth that there is an approximately 40% discordance between what
clinical physicians diagnose as causes of death antemortem and what the
postmortem diagnoses are” (Lunberg, 1998). This is a pretty shocking statistic:
in 4 out of 10 deaths there is a disagreement between what physicians think is
the cause of death prior to autopsy, and autopsy findings. On the other hand, while there are not a lot of
studies done on the effectiveness of persons self-diagnosing and medicating,
what few there are show that with some training the public can be reasonably
good at self-diagnosing certain diseases. One study, for example, showed that
female soldiers with minimal training are comparable to physicians in their
accuracy in diagnosing genitourinary infections (Lowe and Ryan-Wenger, 2000).
Another study revealed that expatriate workers in malaria prone areas were able
to successfully self-test and self-medicate for malaria (Roukens et. al., 2008)
There is also evidence that computer diagnosis of certain conditions can be
significantly better than human diagnosis (Zhang and Lin, 1999, Sordo et. al.,
2002). For example, in a well-known 1971 study, a computer diagnostic system
was pitted against experienced physicians in the diagnosis of acute abdominal
pain: computer diagnosis was 91.1% accurate compared to 79.7% for experienced
physicians (de Dombal et. al., 1972). In another study, computer diagnosis
matched that of neurosurgeons, orthopedic surgeons and general practitioners in
overall average in diagnosing lower back pain. While humans surpassed computers
in non-critical cases, computers surpassed humans in diagnosing more critical
spinal symptoms in which quick intervention is correlated with better outcomes
(Bounds et. al., 1998). In our case, we must imagine that Jill uses a free
diagnostic computer program available on the Internet (funded by charitable
donations, let us suppose). She inputs data about her physical state,
temperature, visible symptoms, etc. and the computer program spits out possible
causes, recommended tests, as well as associated treatments. In her case, the
computer program recommends getting a strep throat test. In sum, the evidence
at hand is circumstantial, but it suggests that a computer diagnosis of common
ailments may approach that of a 15-minute visit to a primary care physician. The much bigger point is that the objection is based
on the wrong contrast class. Consider two questions: 1. How do health outcomes differ for
patient self-diagnosis and self-prescription compared with physician diagnosis
and physician-prescription? (Assume here that patient and physician are never
one and the same.) 2. How do health outcomes differ for
patient self-diagnosis and self-prescription with no medical treatment or
delayed medical treatment? The difference between these two questions can be
illustrated by thinking once more about our In other words, if the objection is at all relevant,
the contrast cannot be between physician diagnosis and self-diagnosis, but
often between self-diagnosis and either no physician diagnosis, or
significantly delayed physician diagnosis. One of the many sad facts about the
plight of the uninsured is that “two-thirds of uninsured women (67%) report
they delayed or went without care they believed they needed in the past year
because they could not afford it” (Kaiser Women’s Health Survey, 2004). The
effects on the health of the uninsured as compared with the insured are quite
dramatic including “estimates attributing to uninsurance an overall increase of
25 percent in mortality risk for working-age adults” (Dorn, 2008). The plight
of many of the poor and uninsured is such that they would have to be pretty
near imbecilic at self-diagnosis and self-medication of antibiotics before
things would not be better for them under SDM. As noted, the benefits of
antibiotics are enormous, and their side effects are typically much less
harmful than the diseases they are used to treat. It may help to think again about our single mother.
Given the statistics just noted, there is a good chance that she will not see a
physician for her sore throat. She may reason that there is a good chance that
it is simply a viral infection, for which the physician may not prescribe
anything. She reasons as well that if she has strep throat she may be able to
fight it off naturally. She realizes, too, that there is some chance that she
has strep throat and that she could get so sick that she will require
hospitalization. The uncertainty of this outcome, against the certainty that if
she sees a physician her son will not be playing soccer or using the Internet
at home, means she is willing to take the risk. The question is whether SDM is
better for her health than delayed or no physician diagnosis. The dangers to
her health in this instance are fairly limited, mostly to do with complications
from antibiotics if she tests positive for strep. Of course such complications
may happen with a physician diagnosis too. But what should be said to the objection that a
computer diagnosis could miss something that a physician with years of
experience may have picked up on? This question again involves a wrong contrast
class: If she is not likely to see a physician, then the fact that a physician
may have made a different and better diagnosis is entirely beside the point.
This is no more relevant than if we say to someone with medical insurance:
look, if you pay out of pocket to see six specialists for a diagnosis the
result is statistically more likely to be correct than if you just rely on what
your health insurance will pay for, namely, a visit for your sore throat to
your family doctor. The high bar of six specialists confirming the diagnosis is
irrelevant: for what appears to be a routine sore throat, almost no one will
pay out of pocket to see six specialists. Similarly, the high bar of employing
physician services for a sore throat is irrelevant for the poor and uninsured,
since many are not likely to pay out of pocket to see a physician. Also, there is some evidence that the less common a
disease in a population, the better computer diagnoses compare with human
diagnoses. This is not necessarily because of incompetence: if a disease is
rare, a family physician will have little experience with it and perhaps no
knowledge. Computers, of course, can hold massive databases including, perhaps,
all the records of all previous cases. So, there is no reason to suppose that
physicians will necessarily pick up on something that a computer diagnosis will
miss (Brause, 2001). Indeed, increasingly patients use the Internet to suggest
a diagnosis missed by the physician (Alper, 2006). Furthermore, notice that the option for consulting a
physician is not significantly diminished through self-diagnosis. If Jill’s
symptoms do not disappear after a few days she can make the decision to consult
a physician and pay the hefty price for doing so. So SDM and physician
consultation are not mutually exclusive. To the extent that the poor have any
choice in seeing a physician, SDM in no way undermines this choice. In other
words, our present system allows only options A and B above. The proposal under
consideration is to allow A, B and C. Despite what has been said in favor of SDM, this much
must be admitted: it is ultimately an empirical conjecture that the SDM option
would yield better health outcomes for the uninsured. I’ve argued that what
evidence there is supports the conjecture that SDM would be better for the
uninsured than our present state of affairs, but this conjecture is amenable to
further testing. Thus, the experimental question is whether having SDM as an
additional option provides better health outcomes for the uninsured as opposed
to receiving what medical attention the uninsured receive at present. So, the
experimental group would receive instruction on using Internet based software
to self-diagnose and self-medicate for certain conditions, e.g., upper
respiratory infections. This group would be matched with cohorts from the
general population of the uninsured and matched for similar health indices,
e.g., the cohorts would be similar in age, fitness, existence of pre-existing
health conditions, and so on. After six months or so, the health outcomes for
the two groups could be compared. The fact that those in the experimental group
are almost certainly going to have more knowledge about their health, a better
understanding of treatment, and more likely to get treatment, strongly suggests
that the health outcomes of the experimental group will be significantly
better. Given what we know about the poor state of health of the uninsured, it
seems a very good bet that the addition of the SDM option will improve their
condition compared with controls. Notice that the conjecture here is not that the
experimental group will have better heath outcomes than those with insurance.
This is an entirely different question. It could be addressed in the same study
by giving a second experimental group, drawn from the uninsured, medical
insurance for the same period. So, imagine three groups of 1,000 individuals
each. Group A is the control group who receive what little medical care the
uninsured now presently get. Group B would have the option of self-diagnosing
and self-medicating, and Group C would be provided with medical insurance. I
suspect the differences between Group B and Group C would be much less than
some might imagine. Physicians may beat out the software on the diagnoses
stage, but those who are charged with self-diagnosing and self-medicating are
probably more likely to follow through, and so may have an advantage on the
treatment end. (Non-compliance with physician directives for treatment and
follow-up visits can be quite high, e.g., studies show that many patients do
not take the full course of antibiotics prescribed by their physician (McNulty
et al., 2007)). Of course, even if insurance provides much better health
outcomes, it will not affect the present argument one iota, since if it turns
out that patients under physicians’ care have better health outcomes such a
result is irrelevant if people cannot afford their services. An objection might be raised on behalf of public
health. If we permit self-medication, isn’t it likely that antibiotics will be
overprescribed and lead to antibiotic resistance? A preliminary response is
that the question is poorly phrased: we should ask whether there would be
further antibiotic resistance due to over prescription, since over prescription
is presently prevalent with physician prescription (McKee et al., 1999; Ong et
al., 2007). There is an epidemiological and a moral reply to this objection.
The epidemiological reply questions whether the use of antibiotics will increase
for society as a whole. Consider again our mother of two. Suppose she has strep
throat but does not take antibiotics. She will be contagious for weeks compared
to only a few days if she took antibiotics. If she passes strep throat to her
children, who infect several others at school, who infect others, and so on,
the overall use of antibiotics may go up. She may also infect her co-workers,
since she is not likely to take an extended period of time off from work, and
naturally these individuals may infect others, so antibiotic use may rise for
society as a whole. In other words, any tendency to overprescribe will have to
be balanced against the effects on others of not prescribing enough. Again, the
contrast here is not what happens under physicians’ care, because we know that
persons in Jill’s situation routinely forgo medical treatment. The moral response requires us to notice first the
logical structure of the objection itself. In effect the objection says that
the health of the uninsured must be sacrificed for the collective good. Which
is to say that the objection requires the social welfare premise: SW: It is sometimes moral to require the
sacrifice of the welfare of some for the sake of the welfare of the general
community. Some moral and political theories reject this premise
outright, so for them this objection will have no traction. We need not
directly challenge the premise, rather, let us grant SW and see what follows.
Clearly, it is important to ask: Who should sacrifice for the collective good
and how? If antibiotic resistance is less of a problem when physicians have a
monopoly on prescribing, then the correct application of SW is that the
collective good should be achieved by having the rich sacrifice some of their
wealth to ensure universal health care, as opposed to the sacrificing of the
health of the poor by prohibiting SDM for the uninsured. In other words, if
collective outcomes are as important a moral consideration as SW says, then it
is only a morally inverted world that would see these ends achieved by
sacrificing the health of the poorer members of society rather than sacrificing
something from the wallets of the richer members. 4.
Conclusion The conclusion here is reasonably circumscribed: we
have argued that a limited number of persons, the poor and uninsured, ought to
be able to self-prescribe a limited number of medications, such as common
antibiotics, given lack of universal health care. Some may think this is only
the thin edge of a wedge. They are probably right. If the health outcomes of
the poor improve on the SDM proposal then surely expanding the option to others
as a means to reduce health care costs and expanding the range of medications
for self-administration ought to be explored. But it may be protested then that
there is no clear indication of the exact scope of the argument. For instance,
assuming the argument was accepted, what prescriptions should policy-makers
make available for self-prescription for the poor and which should remain
available only by physician prescription? Although important, this question has
not been answered here. But notice also that it need not be answered for
present purposes. Our opponent says that the poor should not be able to
self-prescribe any medicines presently available only by physician
prescription. We need only show a single counterexample to this very general
position. As an analogy: if an opponent claims, “All swans are white,” one need
bring only a single non-white swan to the table to refute the generalization.
Our single counterexample is that the poor and uninsured ought to be able to
self-prescribe common antibiotics like penicillin and erythromycin. This is
consistent with the admission that much more work needs to be done to
understand how the SDM option might be implemented as a matter of policy. I suspect that most policymakers, health care workers
and the voting public will think the SDM alternative absurd. Given the
absurdity of endorsing SDM our argument constitutes a new moral reason for
endorsing reasonable access to physicians’ services: to think otherwise leads
to absurdity. In other words, the reasoning is as follows. Assume (for the
purposes of reductio) that as a society we ought not provide universal health
care. If this is so, then we ought to allow the SDM option. But allowing the
SDM option is absurd, so the original assumption is false. We ought to provide
universal health care. Our argument also provides a prudential reason for
powerful interest groups like the AMA that have historically done little to support
reasonable access to physician’s services: SDM would undermine their monopoly,
and so provides them with some self-interested reasons for endorsing universal
health care coverage. Perhaps the AMA (and their ilk) will be more moved by
prudential considerations. Acknowledgements Thanks to
Jean-Paul Vessel for a (gentle) push to write this up, and to Jamie Bronstein
for comments on an earlier version. Notes 2. Some resort
to self-medicating by buying antibiotics at pet stores, or illegally importing
them from other countries. References Alper, B. S. 2006. Usefulness of online medical information. American Family Physician 74(3): 482-85. Brause, R. W. 2001. Medical analysis and diagnosis by
neural networks. In Medical data analysis,
ed. J. Crespo, V. Maojo and V. Martin, 1-13.
|