Book review: Sam HarrisÕ
The Moral Landscape Russell
Blackford University of Newcastle, NSW;
Editor-in-Chief, Journal of Evolution and
Technology russellblackford@bigpond.com Journal of Evolution and Technology - Vol.
21 Issue 2 – December 2010 - pgs 53-62 The Moral
Landscape: How Science Can Determine Human Values. By Sam Harris. Free Press,
New York, 2010. 291 pp., $26.99 (hardcover). Introduction In recent years, Sam Harris has become a
leading figure in the rational scrutiny of religions and religious cultures,
earning himself a place as a prominent ÒNew Atheist,Ó along with Richard
Dawkins, Daniel Dennett, and Christopher Hitchens. To the extent that the New
Atheism is a genuine social movement, Harris deserves much of the credit for it.
In 2004, he made a dramatic breakthrough when The End of Faith was published by W.W.
Norton. This was a fiercely anti-religious book, targeted especially at
Islam, and emphasizing that religious ideas actually matter because religious
adherents are motivated one way or the other to act in accordance with the
teachings they accept. The breakthrough was in convincing a major trade
publisher to pick up a book like this, and then support it aggressively. Other large
publishers followed suit with high-profile critiques of religion by Dawkins and
others. In The Moral Landscape, Harris pushes his agenda a step further,
examining the nature of morality from a secular viewpoint and offering
prescriptions for change. In particular, he contests the moral credentials of
religion, argues against popular understandings of free will, and savages moral
relativism. He presents an eloquent, passionate, but scholarly defense of his
particular take on the phenomenon of morality; he defends moral realism and a
consequentialist approach to moral thinking. Harris argues that science can
give us the information we need to critique moral systems and develop public
policy. If he has his way, much of our moral thinking in the liberal
democracies of the West will change quite radically; in particular, we will
reject the detached and quietest attitude taken by many Western intellectuals
to traditional moral systems. The Moral
Landscape is an ambitious work that will gladden the hearts, and strengthen
the spines, of many secular thinkers. I enjoyed this book, and I
recommend it highly. Though it contains much technical material, from
neuroscience as well as philosophy, Harris makes it all accessible. He has an
enviable gift for vivid phrasing and clear exposition of difficult concepts,
and he undoubtedly has much to teach us. Almost anyone could benefit from
reading The Moral Landscape. In that
sense, I need go no further. Is this book worth obtaining and reading?
Emphatically yes. Serious
reservations about a good book That said, I have serious
reservations. Having now read the book three times, I find that most of the
interesting things I could say would be explanations of my concerns and disagreements.
Part of the problem, no doubt, is that I would have written a rather different
book if IÕd tackled the same subject, and of course there is often a temptation
for a reviewer to dismiss a book simply for not being what he or she would have
written. IÕm very conscious of that temptation, and I have no wish to be
dismissive, so allow me to emphasize that nothing which
follows detracts from The Moral
LandscapeÕs obvious strengths or those of its author. Many passages are very
convincing: for example, Harris provides a particularly lucid and penetrating
critique of libertarian notions of free will. This alone could stand as an
important contribution to public debate, though even here thereÕs room for
doubt as to what policy prescriptions should follow. Some of
our current policies may be rationalized, by some people, some of the
time, on grounds that invoke libertarian free will. Whether they really depend
on that idea is another matter. If Harris is right, some policies, such as
those relating to criminal justice, may need to be rethought from the ground
up; but it remains to be seen how far theyÕd need to change. In particular,
Harris is very quick to dismiss compatibilist accounts of free will and to
assume that only libertarian accounts can underpin certain widespread moral
intuitions. That remains to be demonstrated. Be that as it may, Harris
sees opponents on two sides. On his right, as it were, are various kinds of
moral traditionalists, some of whom support moral ideas that are intellectually
untenable, destructive of human happiness, and, in some cases, even cruel. On
his left are various kinds of relativists, moral skeptics, error theorists, and
non-cognitivists. He seems to think that the latter play into the hands of the
former, that their theories suck away our ability to engage in moral critique.
That, however, is not necessarily true. It may apply to certain crude kinds of
moral relativism, and Harris is impressive in attacking these, but it neednÕt
be so of more sophisticated theories that are taken seriously by professional philosophers.
Even if moral error theories, for example, are disconcerting, they donÕt necessarily entail any quietism about
tyranny, cruelty, or unjust discrimination. Unfortunately, Harris sees it
as necessary to defend a na•ve metaethical position; and, although the defense
itself is conducted with considerable sophistication, he does not seem to
understand the more sophisticated theories over on his left (or why they are
not necessarily in opposition to his main agenda). As a result, I find some of
the main lines of argument in The Moral
Landscape unconvincing, though I accept many of its practical conclusions. In
particular, Harris is correct to attack popular, philosophically
unsophisticated, forms of moral relativism, and to encourage our hostility to traditional
moral systems that cause suffering and harm. Liberal tolerance has its merits,
but weÕd better make sure weÕre tolerating the right things, things that are
largely harmless. However, Harris reaches these
conclusions only by offering what strikes me as a highly implausible and
ultimately unsustainable account of the phenomenon of morality. That account does
not seem necessary to reach his practical conclusions, or at least something
very like them, but I fear that heÕll convince some readers otherwise. We can
live with a more sophisticated view of morality than the one Harris offers
while getting to a similar place in the end. The problem lies in his
insistence that moral judgments, such as ÒLying in circumstances C is morally
wrong,Ó are straightforwardly and determinately true or false in the same way
as factual statements, such as ÒMy breakfast mug contains coffee,Ó appear to
be. We may tend to think of both kinds of statements in the same way, and it
may be unsettling to realize that morality isnÕt quite like that. If, however, as
IÕm convinced, itÕs not, then weÕd better try to understand how and why itÕs not, and whether there are any important practical
implications. Unfortunately, Harris is impatient with all this, and often
resorts to outright scorn in rejecting considerations that donÕt fit with his
position. The picture
according to Harris Here is how the picture looks
if we go along with Harris. Ordinary factual claims are straightforwardly and
determinately true or false, as are the theoretical claims made by science. So
are moral judgments, and in much the same way. Indeed, moral judgments are
simply claims about the well-being of conscious
creatures – claims that may often depend on scientific evidence. Of
course, Harris acknowledges, we may often face practical difficulties in
establishing whether a claim about
the well-being of conscious creatures is true or
false. In principle, however, there will always be an answer. Compare a claim
about the number of grains of sand on a particular beach or the number of
blades of grass in my neighborÕs lawn. In each case, Harris thinks, there is a
correct answer, as long as the question itself has sufficient precision. It may
be impossibly difficult to ascertain the answer in practice, but we can easily distinguish
between answers that are somewhere in the vicinity from those that are not. Surely thereÕs something
about this that sounds attractive. Morality has something to do with the well-being of conscious
creatures, or so it seems to me. When moral systems lose sight of this, they lose
much of their point (donÕt they?) and are likely to become counterproductive,
harsh, or even cruel. Harris does well to point this out and to argue for it at
length. ItÕs an important take-home lesson. But as IÕll come to, Harris goes
much further. Surely, too, Harris has a
point in arguing that science can inform our choices, including those which we label Òmoral.Ó If our aim is to reduce
suffering, for example, science may offer us information about how to do so. As
we discover more and more about the world, our developing moral
ideas may increasingly be molded by advances in scientific knowledge. Furthermore,
Harris is surely correct to deprecate any clear boundary between science and
other areas of empirical inquiry, such as the investigative work of historians.
He makes the compelling point that rational inquiry into the world around us
(and into our own psychological nature) can provide crucial information for
practical decision-making. We are still a long way, I suggest, from a situation
where we can discard such things as folk understandings of what makes people
happy, our own accumulated experiences as individuals, and insights from
literature; and we must continue to reflect on all of these things. In
principle, however, much useful information can be obtained from more formal
kinds of empirical inquiry. At the same time, however, Harris
overreaches when he claims that science can determine
human values. Indeed, itÕs not clear how much the book really argues such a
thing, despite its provocative subtitle. Harris presupposes that we should be
motivated by one very important value, namely the well-being
of conscious creatures, but he does not claim that this is a scientific result
(or a result from any other field of empirical inquiry). If, however, we
combine this fundamental value with knowledge as to how conscious creaturesÕ well-being can actually be aided, we can then decide how to
act. We can also criticize existing moral systems, customs, laws, political
policies, and so on, if we are informed by scientific knowledge of how they
affect the well-being of conscious creatures. While this is all coherent, Harris
is not thereby giving an account of how science can determine our most
fundamental values or the totality of our values. If we presuppose the well-being of conscious creatures as a fundamental value,
much else may fall into place, but that initial presupposition does not come
from science. It is not an empirical finding. Thus, even if we accept
everything else in The Moral Landscape,
it does not provide an account in which our policies, customs, critiques of
policies and customs, and so on, can be determined solely by empirical
findings: eventually, empirical investigation runs out, and we must at some
point simply presuppose a value at the bottom of the system, a sort of Grundnorm that controls everything else. Harris is highly critical of
the claim, associated with Hume, that we cannot derive an ÒoughtÓ solely from
an ÒisÓ – without starting with peopleÕs actual values and desires. He
is, however, no
more successful in deriving ÒoughtÓ from ÒisÓ than anyone else has ever been.
The whole intellectual system of The
Moral Landscape depends on an ÒoughtÓ being built into its foundations. ÒWell-beingÓ This brings me to an obvious
problem in the book, though certainly not the deepest one. For Harris, the key
value from which everything else follows is Òthe well-being of conscious
creaturesÓ; however, itÕs difficult to know just what is meant by Òwell-being.Ó
We get the general idea, of course. It is possible to describe situations where
somebody, or something, is enjoying well-being –
and everyone will agree. ItÕs possible, too, to describe dramatically different
situations where we all recognize suffering and hardship, and weÕll have no
difficulty in concluding that the creatures involved are not enjoying
well-being at all. Things are going badly for them. Harris offers plausible
examples of both classes of situations. Nonetheless, there are cases
where the situation is far less clear. We may find it difficult to judge who
enjoys more well-being than whom. Harris is correct to
point out that this does not have to be fatal to his approach. After all, many other
concepts, such as that of health, are fuzzy around the edges, yet usable in
practice. Perhaps Òwell-beingÓ is like that. We cannot nail the concept down
precisely, but we recognize well-being when we see it,
and we can promote it without worrying too much about precise definitional
niceties. We can also recognize situations where a system of customs or laws is
not promoting well-being and may even be harming it. ThatÕs all fine as far as it
goes, and I would have less problem if Harris put it that way consistently. He
could insist that the point of moral systems is to protect and promote well-being, while acknowledging that well-being is an
inherently fuzzy concept and open to legitimate disagreement at the margins.
The concept might then be a place-holder for something else for which it stands
as a first approximation: it might be a kind of summation of other things that
we value, such as pleasure, satisfaction of preferences, and the possession of
various functional capabilities. Unfortunately, that would not assist Harris in
insisting that moral questions have determinate, objectively correct answers. There
could be situations where the question of which course of action might maximize
well-being has no determinate answer, and not merely because well-being is
difficult to measure in practice but because there is some room for rational
disagreement about exactly what it is. If itÕs shorthand for the summation of
various even deeper values, there could be room for legitimate disagreement on
exactly what these are, and certainly on how they are to be weighted. But if
that is so, there could end up being legitimate disagreement on what is to be
done, with no answer that is objectively binding on all the disagreeing parties. I suggest that this approach
is more plausible than the one taken by Harris himself. Moreover, it need not
produce results greatly different from his own in actual
practice. Our various conceptions of Òwell-beingÓ would not all be
identical, but they would have considerable similarities, which would allow for
much agreement in practical situations. We could reach consensus on many
issues, while also reaching a principled understanding of why total consensus is not possible. Harris, however, appears committed
to the view that there are determinate and objectively correct answers to all moral
questions, even if we cannot discover them in practice. He acknowledges the
theoretical possibility that two courses of action, or, say, two different
systems of customs and laws could be equal
in the amount of well-being that they generate. In
such cases, the objectively correct and determinate answer to the question of
which is morally better would be: ÒThey are equal.Ó However,
he is not prepared to accept a situation where two people who have knowledge of
all the facts could
legitimately disagree on what ought to be done. The closest they could come to
that would be agreement that two (or more) courses of action are equally
preferable, so either could be pursued with the same moral legitimacy as the
other. According to this picture, well-being is something
that has a metric. But what is this ÒsomethingÓ? While Harris is impatient
with what he sees as unimaginative conceptions of well-being,
he needs it to be something that is measurable on a scale, so that objective
comparisons can be made. When the drift of the argument presses him towards defining
well-being, he says that he is not talking about
feelings of pleasure; instead, he tends to invoke ideas of deep satisfaction or
fulfillment. That seems problematic on its face, because it is far from clear
that all conscious creatures are capable of experiencing anything like this. If
they are conscious at all, I suppose that they can experience physical pains
and pleasures, but how much more than that is experienced by, say, an alligator?
We really donÕt know and should not make assumptions. Presumably the metric for
well-being must apply to the most primitive kinds of sensations
as well as to psychological satisfactions and feelings of fulfillment. In the end, I doubt that
there really is a metric that we can use to gain fully determinate answers to questions
of what will maximize well-being. As I suggested
above, however, we donÕt need this in practice. We can obtain information about
such things as physical pleasures and pains, psychological suffering, feelings
of fulfillment, and someoneÕs objective ability to do things and achieve goals,
without believing that all of these can be reduced to a single metric. The information
will still be useful in guiding actions and policies, in criticizing laws and
customs, and so on, and it will often guide us to agreement among ourselves. In
some cases, most or all of the information will point in the same direction. At
a minimum, we should be able to rule out many actions and approaches, and to condemn
many existing social arrangements. Some disagreement may remain, but surely we
can live with that. After all, weÕd need to live with practical disagreements even
if well-being did have a metric,
since even then, weÕd often be plagued by the problems of practical
measurement. Are moral
judgments objectively binding? As IÕve indicated, however,
the definition and measurement of well-being is not my
deepest objection to the Harris approach. For the sake of argument, and as
implausible as it may seem, letÕs assume that well-being
is a single thing that can be specified and quantified. We can assume that, at
least in principle, there is always a correct and determinate answer as to what
course of action (an individual choice or a political policy, for example, or
the continuation or abandonment of a traditional custom) will maximize overall well-being for whatever conscious creatures are affected. Even
so, it is not obvious that I should, in any particular set of circumstances,
adopt the course of conduct with that effect. Why, for example, should I not
prefer my own well-being, or the well-being of the
people I love, to overall, or global, well-being? If it comes to that, why
should I not prefer some other value altogether, such as the emergence of the Ubermensch, to the maximization of
global well-being? Thus there might be a
determinate, objectively correct answer to what maximizes global well-being, but
no such answer to the ancient questions, ÒHow am I to act?Ó and ÒHow am I to live?Ó
ItÕs these questions that really
matter, if weÕre looking for guidance for our actions. Harris never provides a
satisfactory response to this line of thought, and I doubt that one is
possible. After all, as he acknowledges, the claim that ÒWe should maximize the
global well-being of conscious creaturesÓ is not an empirical finding. So what
is it? What in the world makes it true? How does it become binding on me if I
donÕt accept it? Sometimes Harris seems to
think that the course of conduct which maximizes global well-being is the
morally right one because Òmorally rightÓ just means something like Òsuch as to maximize global well-being.Ó But
this wonÕt do. ItÕs no use telling somebody (weÕll call her Alice) to act so as
to maximize global well-being on the ground that this is the morally right
thing to do, while also telling her that
Òmorally rightÓ just means Òsuch as
to maximize global well-beingÓ: the upshot is that Alice is told to act to
maximize global well-being because this will maximize global well-being! ThatÕs
circular. If she is more committed to a goal such as maximizing her own well-being, or that of her loved ones, than to maximizing
global well-being, she is not thereby making a mistake about anything in the
world. Nor is she doing anything self-defeating if she maximizes her own well-being, or that of her loved ones, whenever these
conflict with maximizing global well-being. Nor is she necessarily making
any mistake about the world, or doing anything self-defeating, if she chooses
to assist the emergence of the Ubermensch,
should that goal clash, in a specific case, with maximizing global well-being.
Global well-being is simply not what she most desires
or what she prioritizes as her goal. As she might tell us, ÒEnd of story!Ó Maximizing global well-being,
whatever that really amounts to, may have some
attraction for most or all of us, but someone who cares more about something
else, and acts accordingly, does not thereby make a mistake about the world or
do anything self-defeating. If she is told that she should adopt course of
action X because it will maximize global well-being, she may, quite rationally,
point out that she prefers to adopt course of action Y because it will maximize
her own well-being and that of her loved ones – and that this is her
higher priority. ItÕs no use telling her that course
of action X is the morally right one if it becomes apparent that that just means Òthe course of action that will
maximize global well-being.Ó She can adopt the translation of Òmorally rightÓ
and ask again why she should maximize global being. LetÕs tease this out a bit
further. If Òmorally rightÓ meant something like Òwhat people should actually
do, all things considered,Ó it would, of course, be incoherent for Alice to ask
whether she should do the morally right thing. This would translate to the
nonsensical, ÒWhy should I do what I should do, all things considered?Ó
However, on the theory weÕre considering, Òmorally rightÓ does not mean this. If Òmorally rightÓ means
something like Òsuch as to maximize global well-beingÓ
it becomes coherent for Alice to ask why she should do the morally right thing.
It translates to the perfectly coherent and understandable question, ÒWhy
should I act in such a way as to maximize global well-being?Ó At one point, Harris toys
with the rather desperate idea that even the word Òshould,Ó or the expression
Òought to,Ó can be translated along the lines that ÒYou should do X,Ó or ÒYou
ought to do XÓ means ÒX will maximize
global well-being.Ó Apart from the inherent implausibility of this for any
competent speaker of the English language, it misses the point. Suppose we
assigned that meaning to the word ÒshouldÓ: we could then translate the
question ÒWhy should I act in such a way as to maximize global well-being?Ó as
the ludicrous, ÒDoes acting in such a way as to maximize global well-being
maximize global well-being?Ó Of course it does, but this gets us nowhere. When Alice
proposes to do Y, even though alternative course of action X will maximize
global well-being, she is not asking us which of the possible courses of action
will, in fact have that effect. She already knows
this. Her question is, in effect,
ÒWhat is that to me?Ó How, she wants to know, is she rationally required to act
against her preference? How, for example, is she acting against a standard that
she herself accepts? Or what vital information about the world is she still
missing? Or how will her proposed course of action frustrate her own goals or
otherwise be self-defeating? As Richard Joyce argues in detail in his splendid
book The Myth of Morality (2001), a
point can be reached where someone like Alice is not failing to understand
anything or acting against her own standards or frustrating her own goals (even
if her behavior is socially frowned upon, she may, quite correctly, believe
that she can get away with it in this case). Under those circumstances, there
is a sense in which the prescription to adopt course of action X is not rationally binding on her. She is not
failing to understand anything. And unless
we cheat by invoking a standard of rationality that is already moralized in
some way, she is not doing anything irrational
when she goes ahead with action Y. If we want to persuade Alice
to take action X, we need to appeal to some value (or desire, or hope, or fear,
etc. ... but you get the idea) that she actually has. Perhaps we can appeal to
her wish for our approval, but that wonÕt work unless she actually cares about
whether or not we approve of her. She is not rationally bound to act in the way
we wish her to act, which may be the way that maximizes global welfare, unless
we can get some kind of grip on her own actual values and desires (etc.). Harris does not seem to understand
this idea. In a long endnote to The Moral
Landscape, he accuses J.L. Mackie of making an elementary error in developing
the idea in his celebrated Ethics:
Inventing Right and Wrong (1977). Harris says, ÒClearly, Mackie has
conflatedÓ two notions of objectivity and subjectivity. Leaving aside HarrisÕ habitual
over-reliance on the words ÒclearÓ and Òclearly,Ó often to support assertions that are not clear at all, Mackie makes no
such error. Mackie does not confuse the
idea that talk about morality relates to our experience (and is in that sense ÒsubjectiveÓ)
with the idea that it is therefore biased or merely personal (ÒsubjectiveÓ in a
different sense). The point IÕve been making, and which Mackie makes throughout
Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, is
that claims about how we should act are not rationally binding on us
irrespective of such things as our actual values and desires. Putting it
another way, they are not objectively
prescriptive. Alice is never rationally
bound to act so as to maximize global well-being,
if she actually places a higher priority on something else, such as maximizing
the well-being of herself or her loved ones. That is what is frequently meant,
including by Mackie, when philosophers say that morality is not Òobjective.Ó As
Richard Joyce shows, there is always room for questions such as ÒWhat is that
to me?Ó There can, as Harris states,
be objectively true facts about peopleÕs
subjective experience. But Mackie and Joyce are not disputing this. Their
point is that there are no judgments about how people like Alice should conduct
themselves that are binding on them as a
matter of fact or reason, irrespective of such things as what they actually value,
or desire, or care about. Of course, Alice might be
told to act in such-and-such way – to do X for example – on the
basis that it is a requirement of the law, or of the rules of etiquette, or the
customs of her society, or perhaps the moralized expectations of people in her
sub-culture and social class. There is then a sense in which she is objectively
bound to conform to an institutional norm. That is, there will be an objective
fact as to whether she has breached the norm or not. But that is not very
interesting: even the crudest moral relativists do not deny that people really
can breach, or else conform to, institutional norms. But Alice may not be psychologically
committed to obeying the institutional norm, and she may be prepared to accept
whatever penalty may be imposed for its breach. She may even be in a position
to evade it. Perhaps she can be made to conform if she fears the penalty, but even
this will require an appeal to her desires: her reasons for conformity will not
transcend the social institution and her psychological aversion to punishment. This is important, because it
demonstrates why no one can ever say, coherently, ÒYou just should do X.Ó That is not a coherent notion because it is
always possible for Alice to ask such things as what she is still misunderstanding,
or what she is doing that is self-defeating, if she goes ahead and instead does
Y. If we are going to provide her with reasons to act in a particular way, or
to support a particular policy, or condemn a traditional custom – or
whatever it might be – sooner or later we will need to appeal to the values,
desires, and so on, that she actually has. There are no values that are,
mysteriously, objectively binding on us all in the sense I have been
discussing. Thus it is futile to argue from a presupposition that we are all rationally
bound to act so as to maximize global well-being. It
is simply not the case. Of course, many of us will
form an adverse attitude toward someone who does not care at all about the well-being of others. Such a person will probably not be
good to have around – indeed, she will be a
danger to the rest of us. But she is not necessarily making a mistake about
anything. In any event, Alice may not be like that – not on the
information provided so far. Perhaps her favored course of action Y will
contribute less to global well-being than course of
action X, but only by a small amount. If Alice chooses course of action Y, some
significant number of people will, let us say, end up less happy than might
have been the case if sheÕd chosen action X. But perhaps action X, while providing
a slightly greater amount of (net) global well-being
than course of action Y, will produce considerable pain and suffering for one
of AliceÕs children (and thus for Alice herself). In those circumstances, AliceÕs
course of action may be quite rational,
given her goals, but, more than that, we are also likely to assess it as reasonable and acceptable to us, even if
we would still prefer that Alice adopt course of action X. In a circumstance such as
this, the well-being of Alice and her child is, as it
were, in competition with that of certain others. However, we usually accept
that people act in competition with each other, each seeking the outcome that most
benefits them and their loved ones. We donÕt demand that everyone agree to
accept whatever course will maximize the well-being of
conscious creatures overall. Nothing like that is part of our ordinary idea of
what it is to behave morally. By everyday standards, Alice is not beyond the
pale; she is not someone not worth talking to and socializing with. By everyday
standards, she is not an immoral person, and course of action Y is not morally
forbidden. Moral systems
and their demands This brings me to the
important point that actual systems of moral norms do not make superlative
demands such as the demand that we act to maximize the global well-being
(whatever that is, exactly) of conscious creatures. Rather, they permit us to
act as we wish within certain boundaries that may differ considerably, from
system to system, in how restrictive they are. Some actions will be compulsory,
others will be forbidden, but the remainder are left
to the discretion of the individual concerned. There may also be actions that
are praised or frowned upon, but not required or forbidden. And there may be
more complex ideas of good character, relating to the dispositions of
individuals to act ÒwellÓ or ÒbadlyÓ in the various circumstances that arise.
Some moral systems are very prescriptive indeed, but they all leave at least
some room for competition, conflict, and individual discretion. Though it is difficult to
prove to a high degree of certainty one way or the
other, I suggest that these systems do not, in fact function (indirectly and ineffectually)
to maximize global well-being. They are likely to have less glorious, more
down-to-earth social functions, and they permit biases towards ourselves and loved ones. Even when moral norms and systems
seem aimed at rather broad goals, such as ameliorating suffering, these goals are
likely to be limited. It is one thing to follow a norm of avoiding unnecessary
suffering, or taking steps to reduce it; itÕs quite another to set aside oneÕs
personal priorities and biases, and to aim at some kind of global maximization
of fulfillment or satisfaction. In the upshot, we can ask what
is the point of morality and not
expect a single, fully determinate answer. We can say with confidence that moral
systems do not have so ambitious a point as the maximization of global well-being, but it is difficult to be specific as to what
they do or ought to aim at, short of this. They seem to relate to a number of things
that tend to matter to human beings, given our nature as social animals with an
evolved psychology (and with certain abilities and limitations). Moral systems,
and associated bodies of custom and law, provide us a degree of personal security,
enhance the prospect of (at least intra-societal) peace, and assist social cooperation.
They may go further and aim more broadly at amelioration of suffering. Some of
the ways all this is done can be seen across many societies and cultures:
methods of allocating property, restrictions on the use of violence and fraud,
and so on. That is not to say that just anything can be the point of moral
system, or that itÕs all just arbitrary. Given our nature as social animals
with certain abilities, limits, propensities, and physical needs, it is
unsurprising if the contents of actual moral systems have commonalities.
Similar sorts of restrictions on human conduct (and similar requirements or
obligations) are likely to be needed in many sorts of physical and cultural
environments, and in many economic and technological circumstances. However,
moral systems, and the values by which we assess them, can be non-arbitrary without those values being
fully determined by an objective reality, independent of peopleÕs actual values
and desires. To make this point is not to
deny that there is, in principle, an objectively true description of the nature
of morality as a familiar social phenomenon. On the contrary, I have just given
what I believe to be the beginnings of such a description. There are truths
about the phenomenon of morality, just as there are truths about other things,
but one of the truths about morality is that thereÕs a sense in which we are
not objectively bound by moral norms. I expect that most educated people have a
suspicion that something about morality is ÒsubjectiveÓ or ÒrelativeÓ or Ònot
objective,Ó even if they canÕt quite put their fingers on it. And yes, there is
something to the suspicion, but when we nail down what that actually is we need
not be alarmed. It does not make morality just
arbitrary or capable of taking any
form. It doesnÕt prevent us developing coherent, rational critiques of
various systems of laws or customs or moral rules, or persuading others to
adopt our critiques. All this may be
disconcerting, since it overthrows na•ve ideas of morality. It may even mean
that ordinary first-order moral claims are literally false, to the extent that they
assert (or are heard to assert) their own objective prescriptivity or
bindingness. My analysis will meet much resistance, emotional as well as
intellectual, but why, on deeper reflection, is it terribly surprising? Many of
our value judgments are non-arbitrary without involving fully determinate,
objectively correct answers. No one expects that
kind of answer to a bald question such as, ÒWhat is the best refrigerator?Ó
or ÒWhat is the best motor-car?Ó Our criteria for judging the merits of
refrigerators and motor-cars are not arbitrary, but
nor are they reducible to a metric that weÕre all objectively bound to employ.
Judgments about refrigerators and motor-cars can be
rational and defensible, but there is also room for legitimate disagreement. As
manufacturers know, we all want very similar things from motor-cars
(or refrigerators) but we neednÕt all want exactly
the same things. Something like this applies
to judgments of the merits of Victorian novels, 1950s science fiction movies,
stage actors, paintings and sculptures, houses and gardens, friends and lovers,
computer firms, mathematics teachers, philosophers, pet cats and dogs, sunsets,
public speakers, winter holidays, rose varieties, pop songs, academic journals,
cake recipes, photographs of SaturnÕs rings, and most other things whose merits
concern us at all. Conclusion Despite my criticisms, Harris
is correct on the most important point. We can criticize other cultures as well
as our own. Popular moral relativism notwithstanding, we need not adopt a
quietism about moral traditions that cause hardship and suffering. Nor need we
passively accept the moral norms of our own respective societies, to the extent
that they are ineffective or counterproductive or simply unnecessary. In particular, it is quite
open to us to condemn traditional systems of morality to the extent that they
are harsh or cruel, rather than providing what most of us (quite rationally)
want from a moral tradition: for example that it ameliorate suffering, regulate
conflict, and provide personal security and social cooperation, yet allow
individuals a substantial degree of discretion to live their lives as they
wish. We donÕt all have to agree on exactly what weight to give to these, or
whatever other things of a similar kind we might want from a moral tradition.
Even without total agreement on the point
of morality and on exactly what we
want from a moral tradition, we are quite capable of converging on similar
judgments in many real-world cases. We can, for example, agree to repudiate,
and speak out against, any system of norms that suppresses female sexuality –
and womenÕs freedom more generally – through genital mutilation,
veiling, and social isolation. More generally, we can step
back and ask whether a societyÕs rules, customs, and laws are actually
contributing to the sorts of outcomes that we can (non-arbitrarily) want from
them. At the other extreme, we can ask whether they are producing frustration, hardship,
and suffering. Unfortunately, many societies
rationalize their moral traditions on a false basis, such as portraying their
moral rules as the commands of a deity. Many people may come to believe that
obedience to the supposed deity is the real point of the rules that they follow
and seek to impose on others. Convincing them otherwise may be impossible without
changing their comprehensive understandings of the world, which may, in turn,
not be practicable if they have been thoroughly socialized into a particular
viewpoint from childhood, or if they have a deep emotional investment in it.
But why should that be surprising?
Even if Harris were correct in his strongly realist account of the phenomenon
of morality, he would face a pressing difficulty: that of getting people with deeply
entrenched worldviews that are radically different from his to adopt his broadly
utilitarian account of normative ethics ... without first abandoning their
religious or metaphysical views. In the end, Harris provides a
compelling argument for selective intolerance toward harsh moral traditions. He
argues via a kind of moral realism, linked to a form of utilitarian ethic, but I
submit that these are not doing the real work. To reach a similar conclusion,
we can rely on much weaker premises. ItÕs enough that we have a non-arbitrary
conception of what morality is for, and what sorts of things we can rationally
and realistically want moral traditions to do. Where they divert from that
conception, moral traditions merit our critique and opposition. These should be
every bit as severe, absolutely as passionate, as Harris evidently wants, but
that does not commit us to his total picture of moralityÕs landscape. Like it or not, morality is a
much trickier phenomenon. References Harris, S. 2010. The moral landscape: How science can
determine human values. New York: Free Press. Joyce, R. 2001. The myth of morality. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong.
London: Penguin. |