The Overhuman in the Transhuman
Max More Strategic philosopher, The Proactionary Project max@maxmore.com Journal
of Evolution and Technology - Vol. 21 Issue 1 – January 2010 - pgs 1-4 Abstract Stefan Sorgner (2009) says that on becoming familiar with transhumanism, he Òimmediately thought that there were many
fundamental similarities between transhumanism and
NietzscheÕs philosophy, especially concerning the concept of the posthuman and that of NietzscheÕs overhuman.Ó
In contrast to Bostrom (2005), Sorgner
sees significant and fundamental similarities between the posthuman
and the overhuman. (I will adopt his use of ÒoverhumanÓ in place of ÒovermanÓ
or †bermensch.)
This overall view seems to me highly plausible. I agree with most of SorgnerÕs comments in this respect. My intent is to give
further support to the conceptual parallels. In addition, I argue that these
are not merely parallels: transhumanist ideas were
directly influenced by Nietzsche. Introduction Should
transhumanists look upon Friedrich NietzscheÕs thought as an embarrassment – just as Nietzsche suggested the ape was
to man? Is there an abyss between his Òphilosophy
with a hammerÓ and the philosophy of transhumanism? Stefan Sorgner (2009) says
that on becoming familiar with transhumanism, he Òimmediately
thought that there were many fundamental similarities between transhumanism and NietzscheÕs philosophy, especially
concerning the concept of the posthuman and that of
NietzscheÕs overhuman.Ó In contrast to Bostrom (2005), Sorgner sees
significant and fundamental similarities between the posthuman
and the overhuman. (I will adopt his use of ÒoverhumanÓ in place of ÒovermanÓ
or †bermensch.) This overall
view seems to me highly plausible. I agree with most of SorgnerÕs
comments in this respect. My intent is to give further support to the
conceptual parallels. In addition, I argue that these are not merely parallels: transhumanist
ideas were directly influenced by Nietzsche. First, it is necessary to note that an
enormous range of ideas can be found in NietzscheÕs writing, some of which
– especially comparing different periods of his work – may be
inconsistent. Although there are clear parallels between NietzscheÕs thinking
and some core transhumanist ideas, the latter are
inspired very selectively by the former. Perhaps the most salient example
of a Nietzschean
idea alien to transhumanism is his Òeternal
recurrence.Ó Nietzsche thought this idea inseparable from that of the overman (or overhuman). Many scholars have been puzzled at this
connection and have often rejected eternal recurrence. NietzscheÕs attachment
to the concept probably results from his seeing it as the ultimate affirmation
of the real world as against the Christian (and Platonic) denial of the primacy
of the actual, physical reality. Not only is eternal recurrence a bizarre piece
of metaphysics in itself, it was part of NietzscheÕs denial of the idea of
progress. Both for its inherent implausibility and for its opposition to
progress, this concept cannot be reconciled with transhumanism.
Nevertheless, several other concepts can be so reconciled. As a strong opponent
of philosophical systems, Nietzsche could hardly object to transhumanismÕs
picking and choosing from among his thoughts. Direct influence SorgnerÕs essay
establishes parallels between transhumanism and
NietzscheÕs thought, but does not address the question of whether transhumanist ideas were directly influenced by
Nietzsche. I can state with complete confidence that such an influence does
indeed exist. I know that because his ideas influenced my own thinking. That
thinking led to my introduction of the term ÒtranshumanismÓ
(only later did I discover HuxleyÕs prior use of the term), to the publication
of my essay, ÒTranshumanism: Towards a Futurist
PhilosophyÓ (More 1990), and to my original transhumanist
statement, ÒThe Extropian PrinciplesÓ (later ÒThe
Principles of ExtropyÓ, More 1990b). While these
essays are far from the only sources of contemporary transhumanism,
these seminal writings have been influential. Since they were themselves
influenced by some of NietzscheÕs core ideas, the direct connection between transhumanism and Nietzsche is established. In ÒTranshumanism: Towards a Futurist Philosophy,Ó for
instance, I wrote that ÒThe religionist has no answer to the extropic challenge put by NietzscheÕs Zarathustra: ÔI teach
you the overman. Man is something that is to be
overcome. What have you done to overcome him?ÕÓ Sorgner
notes, ÒThe overhuman represents the meaning of the
earth. The overhuman is supposed to represent the
meaning-giving concept within NietzscheÕs worldview which is supposed to
replace the basically Christian worldview.Ó He also states that ÒNietzsche
upheld that the concept of the overhuman is the
meaning of the earth. I think that the relevance of the posthuman
can only be fully appreciated if one acknowledges that its ultimate foundation
is that it gives meaning to scientifically minded people.Ó This again agrees
closely with my ÒTranshumanismÓ essay in which I
wrote: ÒI agree with Nietzsche (in The
Will to Power) that nihilism is only a transitional stage resulting from
the breakdown of an erroneous interpretation of the world. We now have plenty
of resources to leave nihilism behind, affirming a positive (but continually
evolving) value-perspective.Ó Critical rationalism Reflecting its humanist and Enlightenment
roots, transhumanism places an extremely high value
on rationality. Especially popular among transhumanists
is critical rationalism. This form of rationalism differs from the foundationalist certitude of Descartes. In its most consistent
form it becomes pancritical rationalism (Bartley
1984). As Sorgner points out, Nietzsche, too, had an
immense respect for critical thinking and valued scientific inquiry highly. In my 1994 talk on pancritical
rationalism at the first Extropy Institute conference
(More 1994), I started by citing NietzscheÕs statement: ÒA very popular error:
having the courage of oneÕs convictions; rather it is a matter of having the
courage for an attack on oneÕs convictions!Ó I might just as easily have cited
another passage: ÒConvictions are more dangerous foes of truth than lies.Ó Or
the passage from The Gay Science
(Nietzsche 1882): ÒNot to question,
not to tremble with the craving and joy of questioning É that is what I feel to
be contemptible, and this feeling is
the first thing I seek in everyone: some foolishness persuades me ever and
again that every human being has this feeling, as a human being. It is my kind
of injustice.Ó Although Nietzsche is not essential to critical rationalism, he
does provide inspiration for what might otherwise seem a dry epistemology. Self-Transformation One of the core transhumanist
principles of extropy has been that of Self-Transformation.
In a later version of the Principles, this was complemented by the principle of
Self-Direction. Both of these are highly compatible with NietzscheÕs thinking.
They are also influenced by his work, along with that of many other thinkers. Most
centrally, I would point to ZarathustraÕs declaration (Nietzsche 1885): ÒAnd
life itself confided this secret to me: ÔBehold,Õ it said, ÔI am that which must always overcome itself.ÕÓ From both the individual and species
perspective, the concept of self-overcoming resonates strongly with extropic, transhumanist ideals
and goals. Although Nietzsche had little to say about technology as a means of
self-overcoming, neither did he rule it out. And, as a champion of what he saw
as a coming age of science, it is not difficult to see technology as part of
the process of self-overcoming, so long as it is integrated firmly with will
and self-assertion. Self-assertion in this case, of course, being not assertion
of an existing self to preserve itself, but a striving to Òbecome who you areÓ.
New technologies allow us new means of becoming who we are – another step
toward posthuman ideals – and new ways of Ògiving
styleÓ to our character. As Nietzsche put it: Òa great and rare art!Ó Utilitarianism, slave-morality,
and heroic transhumanism The sole reason Bostrom
(2005) gives for saying that transhumanism has merely
Òsome surface-level similarities with the Nietzschean
visionÓ is that transhumanism – thanks to its
Enlightenment roots – has an emphasis on individual liberties and a
Òconcern for the welfare of all humans (and other sentient beings).Ó Bostrom is correct about this emphasis, as reflected, for
instance, in the principle of Self-Direction in the Principles of Extropy. Bostrom concludes that transhumanism therefore Òprobably has as much or more in
common with NietzscheÕs contemporary J.S. Mill, the English liberal thinker and
utilitarian.Ó Nietzsche famously had nothing positive
to say about the utilitarians. When he mentioned them,
it was to say something caustically critical, such as: ÒMan does not strive for
pleasure; only the Englishman doesÓ (Nietzsche 1889). Should we infer from
NietzscheÕs distaste for the slave-morality of utilitarianism (which turns every moral agent into a
slave yoked to the task of maximizing the greatest good of the greatest number) that transhumanism has little in common with NietzscheÕs
thinking? I think not. What we can infer is that differing
variants of transhumanism are possible. Certainly
there is no inconsistency between transhumanism and a
utilitarian morality. But neither is there any inconsistency between transhumanism and a more Nietzschean
view of morality. While Nietzsche viewed morality as essentially perspectival,
we can easily enough fit him loosely within the virtue ethics approach
classically represented by Aristotle. Yes, transhumanism
can be sanitized and made safe so that it fits comfortably with utilitarian
thinking. Or we can take seriously NietzscheÕs determination to undertake a
Òrevaluation of all values.Ó This not need imply any kind of illiberal
social or political system. It may simply lead to a version of transhumanism that champions the self-overcoming of the
individual without an obligation to
Òthe masses.Ó Many sound pragmatic reasons exist for each of us to want to
uplift everyone – at least for those of us who reject the idea of society
and economy as a zero-sum game. Pragmatic considerations are not the only
reason a Nietzschean transhumanist
may have for benevolence of this kind. Unlike a utilitarian transhumanist
who must regard uplifting others as an obligation, a Nietzschean
transhumanist would look upon the prospect of
uplifting the masses as an expression of overflowing personal power or
well-being or health. Neither a utilitarian nor a Nietzschean transhumanism can
plausibly claim to be the true transhumanism. Both
share the central elements of the radical transhumanist
worldview. My goal has not been to show that transhumanism
must be Nietzschean.
It has been to show that central elements of NietzscheÕs philosophy are not
only compatible with transhumanism, but have
historically had a considerable direct influence on major strands of this
philosophy of life. References Bartley, W. W.
III. 1984. The retreat to commitment.
2nd edition; Chicago: Open Court. Bostrom, N. 2005. A
history of transhumanist thought. Journal of Evolution and Technology 14
(1). Kaufmann, W. A. 1974. Nietzsche:
Philosopher, psychologist, antichrist. 4th edition; Princeton: Princeton
University Press. More, M. 1990, revised 1996. Transhumanism: Towards a futurist philosophy. Extropy 6. <http://www.maxmore.com/transhum.htm> More, M. (1990b revised 2003). The principles
of extropy, version 3.11. Extropy 5.5 (1990 version). <http://www.extropy.org/principles.htm> More, M. 1994. Pancritical
rationalism: An extropic metacontext
for memetic progress. Proceedings of the Extro-1 Conference, Extropy
Institute. Nietzsche, F. 1889. Twilight of the idols. (Available in various editions.) Nietzsche, F. 1885. Zarathustra II 12. (Available in various editions.) Nietzsche, F. 1882. The gay science. (Available in various editions.) Sorgner, S. L. 2009.
Nietzsche, the overhuman, and transhumanism.
Journal of Evolution and Technology 20(1): 29-42. |