Beyond Humanism: Reflections on Trans- and
Posthumanism Stefan
Lorenz Sorgner Department
of Philosophy Journal of Evolution and Technology - Vol. 21 Issue 2 – October 2010 - pgs 1-19 http://jetpress.org/sorgner.htm Abstract I am focusing here on
the main counterarguments that were raised against a thesis I put forward in my
article “Nietzsche, the Overhuman, and Transhumanism” (2009), namely that
significant similarities can be found on a fundamental level between the
concept of the posthuman, as put forward by some transhumanists, and
Nietzsche’s concept of the overhuman. The articles with the counterarguments
were published in the recent “Nietzsche and European Posthumanisms” issue of The Journal of Evolution and Technology
(January-July 2010). As several commentators referred to identical issues, I
decided that it would be appropriate not to respond to each of the articles
individually, but to focus on the central arguments and to deal with the
counterarguments mentioned in the various replies. I am concerned with each
topic in a separate section. The sections are entitled as follows: 1.
Technology and evolution; 2. Overcoming nihilism; 3. Politics and liberalism;
4. Utilitarianism or virtue ethics?; 5. The good Life; 6. Creativity and the
will to power; 7. Immortality and longevity; 8. Logocentrism; 9. The Third
Reich. When dealing with the various topics, I am not merely responding to
counterarguments; I also raise questions concerning transhumanism and put
forward my own views concerning some of the questions I am dealing with. I am very grateful for the
provocative replies to my article “Nietzsche, the Overhuman, and Transhumanism”
(2009), published in the recent “Nietzsche and European Posthumanisms” issue of
The Journal of Evolution and Technologyy
(January-July 2010). In the following nine sections, I will address the most
relevant arguments that have been put forward against some of the points I was
raising. As several commentators referred to identical issues, I decided that
it would be appropriate not to respond to each of the articles individually,
but to focus on the central arguments and to deal with the counterarguments
mentioned in the various replies. I will be concerned with each topic in a
separate section. The sections will be entitled as follows: 1. Technology and evolution;
2. Overcoming nihilism; 3. Politics and liberalism; 4. Utilitarianism or virtue
ethics?; 5. The good life; 6. Creativity and the will to power; 7. Immortality
and longevity; 8. Logocentrism; 9. The Third Reich. 1. Technology
and evolution One of the central issues that
many commentators discussed was the appropriate understanding of who is the
overhuman and how can he come about. In the final paragraphs of his article,
Hauskeller attacks the idea that Nietzsche’s overhuman is to be understood in
an evolutionary sense (2010, 7). However, I can confidently claim that he is
wrong in this respect. Let me list the most important reasons for this. First, Nietzsche
saw human beings as the link between animals and overhumans (KSA, Za, 4, 16).
How is this to be understood, if not in the evolutionary sense? Second, Nietzsche
valued Fourth, many of the
commentators are correct in stressing that Nietzsche regarded education as the primary
means for realizing the overhuman and the evolutionary changes that would enable
the overhuman to come into existence. However, Nietzsche also talks about
breeding in some passages of his notebooks. In my recent monograph on the
concept of human dignity (2010, 226-232), I described in detail how the
evolutionary process towards the overhuman is supposed to occur from
Nietzsche’s perspective. In short, Nietzsche regards it as possible to achieve by
means of education. Thereby, the more active human beings become stronger and
turn into higher human beings, such that the gap between active and passive
human beings widens itself. Eventually, it can occur that the group of the
active and that of the passive human beings stand for two types of human beings
which represent the outer limits of what the human type can be or what can be
understood as belonging to the human species. If such a state is reached, then
an evolutionary step towards a new species can occur and the overhuman can come
into existence. Many transhumanists, by contrast, focus on various means of
enhancement, in particular genetic enhancement, for such an event to occur. In
both cases, the goal is to move from natural selection towards a type of human
selection, even though the expression “human selection” sounds strange – particularly,
perhaps, for many contemporary Germans. Yet, I do not think that human
selection must be a morally dubious procedure. If the selection is a liberal
one, i.e. a type of selection undertaken within a liberal an Even though transhumanist
thinkers and Nietzsche appear to differ over the primary means of bringing
about an evolutionary change, I think the appearance is deceptive. Classical
education and genetic enhancement strike me as structurally analogous
procedures, and in the following section I will offer some reasons for holding
this position. 1.1 Technology Quite a few commentators have pointed
out that that Nietzsche regarded education as the main means of bringing about
the overhuman, whereas transhumanists focus on technological means of altering
human beings to realize the posthuman. Blackford explicitly stresses this in the
editorial of the “Nietzsche and European Posthumanisms” issue: “It is unclear
what Nietzsche would make of such a technologically-mediated form of evolution
in human psychology, capacities, and (perhaps) morphology” (2010, ii).
Certainly, this is a correct estimation. Max More is also right when he stresses
the following: “From both the individual and the species perspective, the
concept of self-overcoming resonates strongly with extropic transhumanist
ideals and goals. Although Nietzsche had little to say about technology as a
means of self-overcoming neither did he rule it out” (2010, 2). Stambler, on
the other hand, goes much further an I can understand Blackford and
More who doubt whether Nietzsche would have been affirmative of technological
means of enhancing human beings. However, Stambler’s remarks concerning
Nietzsche are rather dubious given the current state of the art in Nietzsche
scholarship. Stambler writes that Nietzsche denies scientific knowledge. However,
it needs to be stressed that Nietzsche rejected the possibility of gaining
knowledge of the world, as that is understood within a correspondence theory of
truth, by any method, whether the
sciences, the arts, philosophy or any other means of enquiry, since he held
that each perspective is already an interpretation. It is false to infer from
this that Nietzsche had a disrespect for science. On the contrary, he was well
aware that the future would be governed by the scientific spirit ( Indeed, Nietzsche's respect
for the various sciences is immense. He upholds a theory of evolution which is
based upon a naturalistic worldview that can be summarized by the term “will to
power” ( Is it possible to infer from
Nietzsche’s high estimation of the sciences that he would have been in favor of
enhancement procedures by means of technology? Not necessarily. However, there
are good reasons for holding that the procedures of classical education and
genetic enhancement are structurally analogous. Given that Nietzsche was in favor
of education to bring about the overhuman, and assuming that classical
education and genetic enhancement are structurally analogous procedures, there are
good reasons for concluding that Nietzsche would have been affirmative of
technological means for bringing about the overhuman. I am currently working on
a monograph on the relationship between genetic enhancement and classical
education, and in the following sections I will summarize some of its important
points. 1.1.1
Education and enhancement as structurally analogous procedures Habermas (2001, 91) has criticized
the position that educational and genetic enhancements are parallel events, a position
held by Robertson (1994, 167). I, on the other hand, wish to show that there is
a structural analogy between educational and genetic enhancement such that their
moral evaluation ought also to be analogous (Habermas 2001, 87). Both
procedures have in common that decisions are being made by parents concerning
the development of their child, at a stage where the child cannot yet decide
for himself what it shoul 1.1.1.1
Irreversibility of genetic enhancement According to Habermas, one
claim against the parallel between genetic and educative enhancement is that
genetic enhancement is irreversible. However, as recent research has shown,
this claim is implausible, if not plain false. Let us consider the lesbian
couple discussed by Agar (2004, 12-14) who were both deaf and who chose a deaf
sperm donor in order to have a deaf child (Agar 2004, 12-14). Actually, the
child can hear a bit in one ear, but this is unimportant for my current
purpose. According to the couple, deafness is not a defect, but merely
represents a being different. The
couple was able to realize their wish and in this way managed to have a mostly
deaf child. If germ-line gene therapy worked, then they could have had a non-deaf
donor, changed the appropriate genes, and still brought about a deaf child.
However, given that the deafness in question is one of the inner ear, it would then
be possible for the person in question to go to a doctor later on and ask for
surgery in which he receives an implant that enables him to hear. It is already
possible to perform such an operation with such an implant. Of course, it can be argued in
such a case that the genotype was not reversed, but merely the phenotype. This
is correct. However, the example also shows that qualities which come about due
to a genetic setting are not necessarily irreversible. They can be changed by such
means as surgery. Deaf people can sometimes undergo a surgical procedure so they
can hear again, depending on the type of deafness they have and when the
surgery takes place. One could object that the
consequences of educational enhancement can be reversed autonomously whereas in
the case of genetic alterations one needs a surgeon, or other external help, to
bring about a reversal. This is incorrect again, as I will show later. It is
not true that all consequences of educational enhancement can be reversed. In
addition one can reply that by means of somatic gene therapy, it is even possible
to change the genetic set up of a person. One of the most striking examples in
this context is siRNA therapy. By means of siRNA therapy, genes can get
silenced. In the following paragraph, I state a brief summary of what siRNA
therapy has achieved so far. In 2002, the journal Science referred to RNAi as the
“Technology of the Year,” and McCaffrey et
al. published a paper in Nature
in which they specified that siRNA functions in mice and rats (2002, 38-9).
That siRNA’s can be used therapeutically in animals was demonstrated by Song et al. in 2003. By means of this type of
therapy (RNA interference targeting Fas), mice can be protected from fulminant
hepatitis (Song et al. 2003, 347-51).
A year later, it was shown that genes at transcriptional level can be silenced
by means of siRNA (Morris 2004, 1289-1292). Due to the enormous potential of
siRNA, Andrew Fire and Craig Mello were awarded the Nobel prize in medicine for
discovering RNAi mechanism in 2006. Given the empirical data
concerning siRNA, it is plausible to claim that the following process is theoretically
possible, and hence that genetic states do not have to be fixed: 1. An embryo
with brown eyes can be selected by means of preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD);
2. The adult does not like his eye color; 3. Accordingly, he asks medics to provide
him with siRNA therapy to change the gene related to his eye colour; 4. The
altered genes bring it about that the eye color changes. Another option would
be available if germ line gene-therapy became effective. In that case, we could
change a gene using germ-line gene therapy to bring about a quality x. Imagine
that the quality x is disapproved of by the later adult. Hence, he decides to
undergo siRNA therapy to silence the altered gene again. Such a procedure is
theoretically possible. However, we do not have to use
fictional examples to show that alterations brought about by genetic
enhancement are reversible; we may simply look at the latest developments in
gene therapy. A 23-year-old British male, Robert Johnson, suffered from Leber’s
congenital amaurosis, which is an inherited blinding disease. Early in 2007, he
underwent surgery at In this case, it was a
therapeutic use of genetic modification. As genes can be altered for
therapeutic purposes, they can also be altered for non-therapeutic ends
(assuming one wishes to uphold the problematic distinction between therapeutic
and non-therapeutic ends). The examples mentioned here clearly show that
qualities brought about by means of genetic enhancement do not have to be
irreversible. However, the parallels between genetic and educative enhancement
go even further. 1.1.1.2
Reversibility of educative enhancement According to Habermas,
character traits brought about by educative means are reversible. Because of
this crucial assumption, he rejects the proposition that educative and genetic
enhancement are parallel processes. Aristotle disagrees, and he is right in
doing so. According to Aristotle, a hexis,
a basic stable attitude, gets established by means of repetition (EN 1103a).
You become brave, if you continuously act in a brave manner. By playing a guitar,
you turn into a guitar player. By acting with moderation, you become moderate.
Aristotle makes clear that by means of repeating a certain type of action, you
establish the type in your character, you form a basic stable attitude, a hexis. In The Categories, he makes clear that the hexis is extremely stable (Cat. 8, 8b27-35). In the Nichomachean Ethics, he goes even
further and claims that once one has established a basic stable attitude it is
impossible to get rid of it again (EN III 7, 1114a19-21). Buddensiek (2002,
190) has correctly interpreted this passage as claiming that once a hexis, a basic stable attitude, has been
formed or established, it is an irreversible part of the person's character. Aristotle’s position gets
support from Freud, who made the following claim: “It follows from what I have
said that the neuroses can be completely prevented but are completely
incurable” (cited in Malcolm 1984, 24). According to Freud, Angstneurosen were a particularly
striking example (Rabelhofer 2006, 38). Much time has passed since Freud, and much
research has taken place. However, in recent publications concerning
psychiatric and psychotherapeutic findings, it is still clear that
psychological diseases can be incurable (Beese 2004, 20). Psychological disorders
are not intentionally brought about by educative means. However, much empirical
research has been done in the field of illnesses and their origin in early
childhood. Since irreversible states of psychological disorders can come about from
events or actions in childhood, it is clear that other irreversible effects can
happen through proper educative measures. Medical research has shown,
and most physicians agree, that Post Traumatic Stress Disorders can not only
become chronic, but also lead to a permanent personality disturbance (Rentrop et al. 2009, 373). They come about because
of exceptional events that represent an enormous burden and change within
someone’s life. Obsessional neuroses are another such case. According to the
latest numbers, only 10 to 15 % of patients get cured, and in most cases the
neurosis turns into a chronic disease (Rentrop et al. 2009, 368). Another disturbance which one could refer to is
the borderline syndrome, which is a type of personality disorder. It can be
related to events or actions in early childhood, such as violence or child
abuse. In most cases, this is a chronic disease (Rentrop et al. 2009, 459). Given the examples mentioned,
it is clear that actions and events during one’s lifetime can produce permanent
and irreversible states. In the above cases, it is disadvantageous to the
person in question. In the case of an Aristotelian hexis, however, it is an advantage for the person in question if he
or she establishes a virtue in this manner. To provide further intuitive
support for the position that qualities established by educational enhancement
can be irreversible, one can simply think about learning to ride a bike, tie
one’s shoe laces, play the piano or speak one’s mother tongue. Children get
educated for years and years to undertake these tasks. Even when one moves into
a different country, or if one does not ride the bike for many years, it is
difficult, if not impossible, to completely eliminate the acquired skill. Hence,
it is very plausible that educative enhancement can have irreversible
consequences, and that Habermas is doubly wrong: genetic enhancement can have
consequences that are reversible, and educative enhancement can have
consequences that are irreversible. Given these insights, the parallel between
genetic and educative enhancement gains additional support. 1.1.1.3
Education, enhancement and evolution Can education bring about changes that have an influence on the
potential offspring of the person who gets educated? As inheritance depends
upon genes, and genes do not get altered by means of education, it has seemed that
education cannot be relevant for the process of evolution. Hence, Lamarckism,
the heritability of acquired characteristics, has not been very fashionable for
some time. However, in recent decades doubts have been raised concerning this
position, based on research on epigenetics. Together with Japlonka and Lamb
(2005, 248), I can stress that “the study of epigenetics and epigenetic
inheritance systems (EISs) is young and hard evidence is sparse, but there are
some very telling indications that it may be very important.” Besides the genetic code, the epigenetic code, too, is relevant for
creating phenotypes, and it can get altered by environmental influences. The
epigenetic inheritance systems belong to three supragenetic inheritance systems
that Japlonka and Lamb distinguish. These authors also stress that “through the
supragenetic inheritance systems, complex organisms can pass on some acquired
characteristics. So Lamarckian evolution is certainly possible for them”
(Japlonka and Lamb 2005, 107).1 Given recent work in this field, it is likely that stress,2
education,3 drugs, medicine or diet can bring about epigenetic
alterations that, again, can be responsible for an alteration of cell
structures (Japlonka/Lamb 2005, 121) and the activation or silencing of genes
(2005, 117) The point is that epigenetic variants exist, and are known to show
typical Mendelian patterns of inheritance. They therefore need to be studied.
If there is heredity in the epigenetic dimension, then there is evolution, too.
(2005, 359) They also point out that “the transfer of epigenetic information from
one generation to the next has been found, and that in theory it can lead to
evolutionary change” (2005, 153). Their reason for holding this position is
partly that “new epigenetic marks might be induced in both somatic and
germ-line cells” (2005, 145). A “mother’s diet” can also bring about such alterations, according to
Japlonka and Lamb (2005, 144), hence the same potential as the ones stated
before applies equally to the next method of bringing about a posthuman, i.e.
it is possible that the posthuman can come about by means of educational as
well as genetics enhancement procedures. 1.1.1.4
Nietzsche and Technology Given the above analysis, I
conclude that Habermas is wrong concerning fundamental issues when he denies
that educational and genetic enhancements are parallel events. Even if the
parallel between educational and genetic enhancement is accepted, however, it
does not solve the elementary challenges connected to it, such as questions
concerning the appropriate good that motivates efforts at enhancement. Even though I am unable to
discuss that issue further here, this analysis provides me with a reason to
think that Nietzsche would have been in favor of technological means for
bringing about the overhuman. Nietzsche held that the overhuman comes into
existence primarily by means of educational procedures. I have shown that the procedures
of education and genetic enhancement are structurally analogous. Hence, it
seems plausible to hold that Nietzsche would also have been positive about technological
means for realizing the overhuman. 2. Overcoming
nihilism The next topic I wish to
address is that of nihilism. More mentioned it, and I think that some further
remarks should be added to what he said. I think that More is right in pointing
out that Nietzsche stresses the necessity to overcome nihilism. Nietzsche is in
favor of a move towards “a positive (but continually evolving)
value-perspective” (2010, 2). More agrees with Nietzsche in this respect, and
holds that nihilism has to be overcome. However, before talking critically about
nihilism one has to distinguish its various forms. It is important not to mix
up aletheic and ethical nihilism, because different dangers are related to each
of the concepts. Aletheic nihilism stands for the view that it is currently
impossible to obtain knowledge of the world, as that is understood in a correspondence
theory of truth. Ethical nihilism, on the other hand, represents the judgment
that universal ethical guidelines that apply to a certain culture are currently
absent. To move beyond ethical nihilism does not imply that one reestablishes
ethical principles with an ultimate foundation, but it merely means that
ethical guideline which apply universally within a community get reestablished
(Sorgner 2010, 134-135). Nietzsche’s perspectivism, according to which every
perspective is an interpretation, implies his affirmation of aletheic nihilism
(Sorgner 2010, 113-117). I think Nietzsche’s position is correct in this
respect. Ethical nihilism, on the other hand, can imply that the basis of human
acts is a hedonistic calculation, and Nietzsche is very critical of hedonism
(KSA, JGB, 5, 160). He definitely favored going beyond ethical nihilism, but I
doubt that his vision concerning the beyond is an appealing one. In general, I
find it highly problematic to go beyond ethical nihilism, because of the
potentially paternalistic structures that must accompany such a move. I will
make some further remarks concerning this point in the next section. From my
remarks here, it becomes clear that there are good reasons for affirming both
types of nihilism – in contrast to Nietzsche, who hopes that it will be
possible to go beyond the currently dominant ethical nihilism which he sees
embodied in the last man whom he characterizes so clearly in Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Coming back to aletheic
nihilism, I wish to stress that, like Nietzsche, I regard this type of nihilism
as a valuable achievement and I regard it as the only epistemic position that I
can truthfully affirm. Why is it valuable? Aletheic nihilism helps to avoid the
coming about of violent and paternalistic structures. Religious fundamentalists
claim that homosexual marriages ought to be forbidden because they are unnatural.
What the concept “unnatural” implies is that the correspondence theory
represents a correct insight into the true nature of the world. Political
defenders of a concept of nature act like a good father who wishes to
institutionalize his insight to stop others from committing evil acts. The
concept “natural” implies the epistemic superiority of the judgment to which it
applies. Aletheic nihilism, on the other hand, implies that any judgment and
all concepts of the natural are based on personal prejudices and that each
represents a specific perspective – not necessarily anything more. Religious
fundamentalists commit an act of violence by claiming that x is an unnatural
act, which then implies that those (a, b, & c) who commit act x do some
evil, and thereby these fundamentalists look down upon a, b, and c who suffer
from being humiliated. If we realize that all judgments are interpretations
based upon personal prejudices, it is easier to refrain from universalizing one’s
own values and norms and to accept that other human beings uphol 3. Politics
and liberalism Given the argument of the
previous section, it is not surprising that I was slightly worried when I read
that Roden affirms the move away from “bio-political organizations such as
liberalism or capitalism” (2010, 34). I wonder what is the alternative, because
I think we have done pretty well recently in Western industrial countries with
liberal and social versions of democracy. I do not think that there is nothing
which can get improved or criticized, but generally speaking I am very happy
living in a Western liberal democracy with a well developed health system and
permanently new technological innovations that help us in improving our lives
as long as we do not let ourselves get dominated by these developments. Most other
types of political organization so far have led to paternalistic systems in
which the leaders exploited the citizens in the name of the common good. Any
system that does not sufficiently stress the norm of negative freedom brings
about structures which are strongly paternalistic. I do not think that social
liberal democracies are the final answer to all questions or that they are
metaphysically superior to other types of political organization, but I think
that pragmatically they seem to work pretty well. In addition, I am afraid of
the violence and cruelties related to political structures that are based upon
stronger notions of the public good. An apparent difference between
transhumanism and Nietzsche’s philosophy in this respect is pointed out by Hauskeller,
who stresses that transhumanists aim at making the world a better place,
whereas Nietzsche does not because he supposedly holds that there is no “truly
better or worse,” and so does not aim at bettering humanity (2010, 5). There is
some truth in what Hauskeller says. However, Nietzsche did have a political
vision, even though he also claimed to be a non-political thinker. I think that
his political vision, which I described in detail in my recent monograph (2010,
218-32), is not very appealing, because it leads to a two-class society in
which a small class of people can dedicate themselves to the creation of
culture, while the rest of humanity has to care for the pragmatic background so
that the small group of artists can dedicate themselves to such a life style.
This is Nietzsche’s suggestion of how ethical nihilism ought to get transcended. Given this vision, it seems that
there is a clear difference between Nietzsche’s view and that of
transhumanists. However, I do not think that this is necessarily the case. The
danger of a two-class society also applies to many visions of transhumanists,
especially if an overly libertarian version gets adopted. Transhumanism can lead
to a genetic divide and a two-class society, as has been shown convincingly in
the Gattaca argument. In particular,
a solely libertarian type of transhumanism implies the danger of a genetic
divide that would not be too different from Nietzsche’s vision. Again, I agree with More’s judgment
that the goals of transhumanists and Nietzsche do not have to “imply any kind
of illiberal social or political system” (2010, 4). However, in the case of
Nietzsche it is more plausible to interpret his political vision such that it
is not a very appealing one, because it leads towards a two-class society. This
danger can also arise from an overly libertarian type of transhumanism. James Hughes (2004) has put
forward some plausible arguments why a social democratic version of
transhumanism might be more appropriate. I have some reservations about both social-democratic
and libertarian positions, even though I share many basic premises of both. I
share Hughes’ fear that a libertarian type of transhumanism leads to a genetic
divide. However, I also fear that a social democratic version of transhumanism
might not sufficiently consider the wonderful norm of negative freedom for
which several interest groups have been fighting since the Enlightenment so
that we nowadays can benefit from the results of these struggles. I regard a
dialectic solution as more plausible; this implies that there is no ideal
political system which can serve as the final goal towards which all systems
ought to strive. Any system brings about challenges that cannot get solved
within the system, but they can be resolved by altering the system. As this
insight applies both to libertarian and social democratic systems, a pragmatic
pendulum between those extremes might be the best we can achieve, which also implies
that we permanently have to adapt ourselves dynamically to the new demands of
social institutions and scientific developments. Dynamic adaptation works best
in the process of evolution and might be the best we can achieve on a cultural
level, which includes our political systems, too. Hence, not sticking
dogmatically to one’s former evaluations might not be a sign of weakness, but
of dynamic integrity (Birx 2006). Dynamic integrity enables us
to adapt to new demands and challenges, which arise continually because of the
permanent flux of everything that we have to deal with. However, there ought to
be some stable aspects, too, namely one’s integrity, which consists in the
recognition that the norm of negative freedom is an exceptional achievement that
we always ought to consider. If there arises the need to impose limitations on
negative freedom, then this ought to occur in order to defend and preserve
freedom. If negative freedom leads to unfreedom, we ought to restrict it, so
that it can be preserved. Once there is no need to restrict negative freedom
anymore, we ought to abolish the restrictions that we introduced. Hence, I suggest
that the norm of negative freedom ought to be central in answering the challenges
from bioethical questions. However, once the system brings about a radical
split concerning the people in question, then the norm of equality ought to
receive further consideration. In this way, we would get a dynamic politics that
implies a fluid interplay between negative freedom and equality, or between a
libertarian and a social democratic system. However, the need to permanently adapt
ourselves occurs in the name of freedom. We keep our integrity concerning the
central norm of negative freedom, but we always make additional rules that take
into consideration the contemporary state of affairs, so that the danger of a
genetic divide, or a two-class system such as proposed by Nietzsche, does not
occur. 4.
Utilitarianism or virtue ethics? I greatly appreciate More’s
remarks when he stresses the following: Certainly there is
no inconsistency between transhumanism and a utilitarian morality. But neither
is there any inconsistency between transhumanism and a more Nietzschean view of
morality. While Nietzsche viewed morality as essentially perspectival, we can
easily enough fit him loosely within the virtue ethics approach classically
represented by Aristotle. (2010, 3) More’s point is not only
correct, but also very important. It is true that many transhumanists take a
utilitarian standpoint, and the bioethics debate in the English speaking world
in general is also dominated by this ethical theory. However, this does not mean
that other ethical theories are irrelevant in this respect or have to be inconsistent
with transhumanism. More is also very perceptive
in pointing out that Nietzsche can be seen as a philosopher who is putting
forward a virtue ethics. This does not imply that Nietzsche’s position has much
in common with a traditional virtue ethics like the ones put forward by Plato
or Aristotle. In contrast to those, Nietzsche holds that there are no
universally valid virtues. Yet, he presents a perspectival account of virtues, according
to which there are virtues that apply to certain types of human beings (Sorgner
2010, 119-50). According to Nietzsche, it is possible to name virtues that apply
to members of a certain type, and there are other virtues which apply to a certain
sub-type only, and again others which are solely dependent upon the specific
physiology of an individual. A virtue that Nietzsche upholds for all active
human beings is truthfulness (Sorgner 2010, 125-26). Without having to describe
Nietzsche’s account of the virtues in detail, I wish to stress that his general
approach might also be an appropriate one for transhumanists. So far, mainly
bioconservatives have used a virtue ethical approach: the position put forward
by Sandel is probably the most influential of these. However, instead of
arguing primarily on utilitarian grounds, I regard it as appropriate to base
one’s argument in favor of enhancement technologies on an approach that can be
understood as a type of virtue ethics. In this respect, contemporary ethicists
can benefit immensely from studying Nietzsche. Sandel accepts that many moral
concepts to which traditional ethical discourses have referre I do not think this is the
case. Given the short version of my argument in favor of the structural
analogies between classical education and genetic enhancement, it becomes clear
that genetic enhancement is not as bad as it sounds in the writings of Sandel,
and it also follows that parents who wish to or use technology to bring about
certain structures in their children do not have to be vicious. In fact, the opposite
might be the case. Most, if not all, legal jurisdictions demand that there is a
parental duty to educate one’s children (Allhoff 2009, 32). Given the aforementioned
structural analogy, it follows that if this is the case then there can also be a
parental duty to enhance one’s children (Ranisch and Savulescu 2009, 36-37).
This does not mean that parents ought to alter their children technologically
in all respects. However, it does imply that there can be cases in which it is
appropriate for parents to enhance their children. I do not intend to put
forward a complex argument here concerning this issue, but I am merely trying
to hint at the possibility that it can be bad not to consider the duty to
enhance one’s child, and a parent who disrespects that duty can be referred to
as vicious or rather as someone who does not possess parental virtues. In a
longer version of this paragraph, I would specify in more detail what such an
attitude can imply. For present purposes, I have merely sought to provide some
reasons for holding that virtue ethics can be an ethical theory which goes
along well with a transhumanist basic attitude, and that such an approach might
in some cases be more convincing than an argument based upon utilitarian
foundations. Nietzsche can be a good author for inspiration for formulating such
an approach. 5.
Nietzsche, transhumanism and the good life A topic that has been in the
centre of most ethical theories, at least until the end of the Renaissance, was
that of the good life. The replies to the question of the good put forward by
transhumanists and Nietzsche force us to consider what can be said concerning
the final goal of human acts today. According to Hauskeller (2010, 6), the
transhumanist concept of the good involves a long, happy, and healthy life.
Hence, it is supposedly not very different from what is being widely shared
among many people in Western industrial countries today. Hauskeller stresses
that Nietzsche, on the other hand, claims the following: “What was commonly
regarded as evil needed to be recognized as good” (2010, 6). It can be inferred
from Hauskeller’s remarks that the respective concepts of the good upheld by
transhumanists and by Nietzsche are radically antagonistic. I think the issue is
a bit more complex than that. First, the question of
happiness is a difficult one in Nietzsche. On the one hand, Nietzsche
vehemently criticizes philosophical theories that stress the importance of
happiness (KSA, JGB, 5, 160). On the other hand, we have philosophers such as
Seel – and here I agree with him – who hold that Nietzsche’s main focus is on
the question concerning the good life, and living eudaimoniously (Seel 1998,
27). In fact, Nietzsche did criticize happiness as the goal of human lives.
However, when he employed the concept happiness
he identified it with a hedonistic concept, and he was very critical of many
types of hedonism. Yet, there are even reasons for identifying some elements of
Nietzsche’s ethics with a hedonistic one, given that he aims at the affirmation
of one moment by means of which one’s whole life can get justified. Without
considering this point any further, I wish to stress that Nietzsche’s main
attack was on an enlightened version of happiness, as embodied in the character
of the last man, which can be identified with health, happiness and a long
life. In this respect, Hauskeller is
correct. However, by focusing solely on this point, he takes an overly one-sided
approach. According to Nietzsche, the main goal of all organisms is power: for
Nietzsche, this is open concept that can be identified with various contents,
depending on the perspectival interpretation of an organism as to which concept
of power it applies. What is important for all organisms is the need to
recognize the permanent necessity to overcome themselves, and hence to set themselves
new and higher goals. According to Nietzsche, one of the few detailed elements that
constitutes an elementary aspect of all concepts of the good is the value of
self overcoming, which can be reached by means of one’s embeddedness in a
process of continual interpretation. Yet, it is possible to make some further
comments concerning the good to which Nietzsche subscribes. According to
Nietzsche, the classical ideal of a fully flourishing person with a strong and
creative mind, someone who interprets the world and puts forward the
interpretation in a tempting manner, is the highest concept of power that can
be held (Sorgner 2007, 53-58). I think that this concept is valid only for Nietzsche
himself, but something similar can also be found in the views of transhumanists.
Bostrom stresses the Renaissance ideal as a concept of the good that is worth
aspiring to (Bostrom 2001). Thereby he comes close to what Nietzsche had in
mind for himself. In addition, it is also very different from a simple-minded
way of living a long, happy, and healthy life, because the Renaissance ideal
implies the need to continually work at various aspects of one’s own abilities.
Given further examination, there might be some difference between the respective
concepts discussed by Nietzsche and Bostrom, but there is more shared ground
than Hauskeller recognizes. In any case, there is a danger in upholding such a
concept of the good. According to Nietzsche, the classical ideal is only valid
for himself. According to Bostrom, it is and ought to be a general ideal, I
think, or least one that is valid for all transhumanists. Any ideal which
claims to be universally valid seems dangerous to me. What consequences are
implicit in a concept of the good like the Renaissance ideal, if it is taken as
a universally valid concept? Let us take the famous example
of the deaf lesbian couple who wish to have a deaf child. If one takes an objective
concept of health and accepts that the Renaissance ideal is universally valid,
then we have reasons for not giving the couple the permission to have that
child because deafness is not part of the Renaissance ideal. In general,
transhumanists value negative freedom immensely. However, in such cases as the
one concerning the deaf lesbian couple, there are inevitable conflicts between
the Renaissance ideal of the good and the norm of negative freedom. If one
upholds the Renaissance ideal and one also wishes to give it a legal
underpinning, this will lead to a paternalistic intrusion of the state into the
negative freedom of the citizens – in this case the procreative freedom of the
parents. I do not think that there is anything wrong with the Renaissance ideal
as a personal ideal. However, once it is supposed to serve as normative guideline
for legal decisions, it becomes problematic. The deaf lesbian couple wishes
to make use of their right to procreative freedom, and there is nothing wrong
with that. No one is harmed. They merely realize a concept of the good that does
not correspond to the one held by the majority. It is not, moreover, a concept of
the good that is being upheld solely by a mad individual. There is a culturally
accepted subculture that shares the concept in question, even though many human
beings might not be able to imagine its validity. Here, I think, we have a case
in which it is appropriate to accept the otherness of the members of the group
of the deaf. It is an otherness that many might not be able to imagine, but the
deaf community claim to be able to live a good life the way they live, and why
should someone from the community of the hearing be justified in claiming that
the deaf cannot lead a good life in the
full sense of the word? Concepts of the good that pretend to be universally
valid, and seek acceptance on a legal level, lead to political systems that disrespect
the otherness of minority groups, and I do not think that the state ought to
act violently against members of minority groups. These reflections lead me directly
to the next and related issue. 5.1 New
concepts of the family The Renaissance ideal not only
implies high capacities in various disciplines and areas, but also leading a flourishing private life, being
married and having some children. Hence, it most probably implies being a part
of a flourishing family. Yet, the concept of the family is a difficult one, especially
in the age of biotechnology. FM-2030 stresses that social institutions like the
family become obsolete in scientifically and technologically advanced societies,
as Bainbridge pointed out correctly (2010, 40). I think I know what FM-2030 is
hinting at. Yet, I would rather say that I do not think that families become
obsolete but that their form has to get revised significantly. It is possible
to imagine that a child can have two mothers or two fathers. Maybe, it can even
have two fathers and one mother, or vice versa. Especially when science and
technology progresses even further, it might be possible to compose the genetic
makeup of a child by putting together genetic information from two mothers and
one father who have agreed that they wish to live together and have the
responsibility of bringing up this child. Why should it not be possible
to accept any group of consenting adults to becoming partners? I do not see a
necessary reason why partnership has to be limited to a heterosexual couple or
even a homosexual couple. If there are three, four, or even more consenting
adults who wish to get married and have children, it ought to be possible. I am
not saying that biotechnology advances so fast that that a group of several
adults can become biological parents fairly soon, but if such a group of people
wishes to get married, then this ought to be possible. If such a group wishes
to have a child, and if this is scientifically possible, then a society in
which the right to procreative freedom is respected should allow them to
progress with their endeavors. Hence, biotechnological developments can bring
about the need for significant revision of our concept of a family, and these
revisions will definitely conflict with the Renaissance ideal. Hence, I do not
think that the Renaissance ideal ought to be put forward as a universally valid
one. 6.
Creativity and the will to power There are a couple of remarks
I am bound to make concerning comments by various authors about the basis of
Nietzsche’s concept of the world. I will not go into too much detail in my
replies, but I wish to mention some claims that are highly dubious. When
Blackford writes that Nietzsche holds a “scientific materialist view of the
world” (2010, i), he is not quite right, because Nietzsche was not a
materialist. His will to power theory can be classified, rather, as a teleological
concept of the world, but without having a final telos. It can also be misleading to
claim, as Bainbridge does, that Nietzsche was someone who “doubted the
possibility of progress” (2010, 39). Nietzsche regarded change as a permanent
phenomenon. Like Heraclitus he holds that all things change in all respects in
every moment (Sorgner 2007, 39-65). He did not think it possible to say that
things are permanently getting better. Such a judgment would imply that there
is a universally valid criterion upon which such a judgment can be made, but he
doubted the possibility of such judgments. Still, awareness of his dynamic will
to power worldview should be sufficient to reveal that Nietzsche understood the
world as being permanently in progress in a sense that does not imply that the
future has to be better than the past. In addition, Bainbridge
identifies Nietzsche with someone who affirms “reading novels or poetry” (2010,
39) to bring about better human beings. Nietzsche’s concept of power is far removed
from such a position, because Nietzsche particularly stresses the creative
aspect of existence, rather than the receptive one. His will to power theory
implies that the active creation of new values, embedded in an inclusive theory,
is the highest task by means of which it is possible to achieve the highest
kinds of power ( Hibbard claims that “the
overhuman has no need for improvement, having achieved satisfaction with life”
(2010, 10), but he does not cite any passages which support this claim. As I
mentioned before, the main aspect of Nietzsche’s concept of the good is that of
self-overcoming. It applies to all beings, to higher humans as well as
overhumans. Why should overhumans have no need for improvement? I think Hibbard
makes this one-sided judgment, because he focuses on the claim that overhumans
can get into a situation where they can say Yes
to one moment, and thereby they manage to affirm the eternal recurrence of
everything. However, being able to affirm one moment does not mean that
overhumans have achieved satisfaction in life. Satisfaction is not something
overhumans aim for. They wish to be creative, to permanently overcome
themselves, and to reach higher creative goals (Sorgner 2010, 223-24). Even if
they managed to say Yes to one moment,
there is no reason why they should stop willing to overcome themselves. A further point concerns the
relationship between the eternal recurrence and the will to power theory. More
is right when he claims that the idea of the eternal recurrence is alien to
transhumanism. However, he also holds that it is “inseparable from that of the
overman (or overhuman)” (2010, 1). He is right in explaining that the eternal
recurrence is one of the central aspects of Nietzsche’s thought (Sorgner 2010,
226-32). It is fundamental to his thinking, because it is related to the
question of the meaning of life (Sorgner 2004, 169-88). However, the concepts
of the eternal recurrence and the overhuman are not logically inseparable. If
one does not regard the question concerning a meaning of life as important, it
is still possible to uphold the rest of Nietzsche’s claims, if one wishes to do
so. Then the overhuman would be seen as simply a further step in the
evolutionary process. Hibbard would have some doubts concerning this claim,
because he holds that Nietzsche’s overhumans can never actually come into
existence, but posthumans, as described by transhumanists, can become real (2010,
9). In this context, Hibbard cites Nietzsche’s remark that there is an “infinite
distance” between human beings and overhumans (2010, 9). As an infinite
distance cannot be transcended, it is impossible for overhumans to come into
existence, or so he seems to think. However, if one takes the various
utterances of Nietzsche concerning the overhuman into consideration, Nietzsche’s
remark should be understood metaphorically. According to Nietzsche’s writings,
there have been higher human beings, but there has not yet been an overhuman.
Still, there is nothing in Nietzsche’s writings which renders plausible the judgment
that it is impossible for Nietzsche’s overhumans to come into existence. 7.
Immortality and longevity In contrast to the great
variety of aspects I have had to deal with in the previous section, the
question of immortality and longevity is indeed a specific and a very important
one, and various authors have suggested that Nietzsche and transhumanists hol Transhumanists also aspire for
a type of immortality, though, in most cases, this is not literal immortality
but rather a long life or a prolonging of human lives. Hence, both Nietzsche and
transhumanists reject the idea of an eternal afterlife in a transcendent world
an I wonder whether
transhumanists are committed to longevity as a necessary component of the good
life, and whether it is valid for all human beings that a good life for
posthumans must be a long one. The Transhumanist Arts Statement seems to imply
that transhumanists must uphold longevity as a value, but an alternative would
be to claim that it is up to the individual posthuman what he values. Even from
an evolutionary perspective, the longevity of individuals might not be in the
interest of the species. 8. Logocentrism According to Hauskeller
transhumanists “continue the logocentric tradition of Western philosophy,”
whereas Nietzsche moves away from this tradition by positing that the overhuman
is “entirely body” (2010, 6). Again, Hauskeller is partly right. It has been
recognized widely and correctly that Nietzsche became the ancestor of
postmodernism by going beyond logocentrism (Habermas 1985, 104-129; Vattimo
1988, 164; Sloterdijk 1987, 55) and by stressing the importance of the body.
However, the distinction raised by Hauskeller is based on a selective reading.
Even though Nietzsche moves away from the logocentric tradition, he still
values reason. Like Hauskeller, Bainbridge fails to recognize this; he claims
that most of what Nietzsche wrote “was gloriously incoherent” (2010, 48). In my
monograph Metaphysics without Truth: On
the Importance of Consistency within Nietzsche’s Philosophy (2007), I have explained
in detail why this is not the case and why consistency is important for
Nietzsche. In the following paragraphs I will summarize my analysis. It is true that Nietzsche
seems to be inconsistent when he puts claims that every perspective is an
interpretation, but also that the world is will to power. On the basis of a more
detailed analysis of his writings and the dialectical nature of his approach to
philosophy, however, the apparent inconsistencies dissolve. For Nietzsche, every
perspective is an interpretation, and this applies to all the things Nietzsche
says, too. However, this does not imply that a judgment is false, but merely
that it can be false. As long as no one has shown that one judgment concerning
the ultimate foundation of the world is true, Nietzsche’s perspectivism is a
plausible theory of knowledge, and I do not think that one fundamental truth
about the world has been discovered. Does this mean that Nietzsche’s position
might also apply to reason and the demand to make consistent judgments? Yes, I
think this is the case, but this does not imply that reason is without value.
Reason might not be able to provide us with an understanding of the truth in
correspondence with the world. However, it developed in the process of
evolution because it was in our interest to have this capacity. Reason is a
faculty that helps us to survive, and it enhances our ability to become more
powerful. It is this line of thought which Nietzsche uses to explain why reason
and consistency are important. Reason might not help us in our task of getting
a better understanding of the world, but it helps us to better deal with the
world in which we are living. I think that this Nietzschean view of the
importance of reason is plausible and convincing. I think, too, that many
transhumanists could agree with Nietzsche in this respect. Our capacity to reason
is not connected to an entity that separates us from the naturalistic world,
but it is a capacity which is embedded in this world. Varela, Thompson and
Rosch (1991) try to develop a naturalistic and evolutionary account of the mind,
and it is to this endeavor that both Nietzsche and many transhumanists could
subscribe. I definitely think it is a path worth taking because I share their
naturalistic sympathies. If transhumanists, too, have
sympathies for evolutionary accounts of the mental, then it would be false to
claim that transhumanist continue the “logocentric tradition of Western
philosophy,” because that tradition holds that human beings possess a logos which separates them categorically
from the natural world and provides them with a special status in the world. On
this view, human beings are categorically different from other natural
entities. I doubt that this is a view many transhumanists would subscribe to. 9.
Nietzsche and the Third Reich At this stage we are coming to
what I see as the real motive for Bostrom’s claim that Nietzsche cannot be seen
as an ancestor of transhumanism (2005, 4). Nietzsche still has a rather unsavory
reputation in many social circles. The philosophical reaction to the
Sloterdijk-Habermas debate that took place as a result of Sloterdijk’s talk on
the “Rules concerning the Human Zoo” revealed that many German philosophers continue
to see Nietzsche as a type of proto-fascist (Sorgner 2000, 10-13). Even though
this position is regarded as absurd by most serious Nietzsche scholars,
especially in the English speaking world, the educated public, too, seems to
associate Nietzsche with the fascism of the Third Reich. Some phrases from the JET issue on “Nietzsche and European
Posthumanisms” seem to go in a similar direction. Stambler affirms Fedorov’s
reading of Nietzsche as a “mouthpiece of militarized Perhaps in using the phrase “German
aristocratism” Stambler refers to the attitude of some Germans, some time ago,
who regarded themselves as superior to other nations – or in other words,
German fascism. In that case, his judgment would imply that there are
connections between the world views of Nietzsche and German fascism. A similar
estimation of Nietzsche’s philosophy is put forward by Bainbridge, which becomes
clear in the following remark about Nietzsche: “Perhaps he really was a Nazi” (2010,
37). I wonder what Bainbridge means by this. Nazis are people who supported
Hitler as political leader. Nietzsche was definitely no Nazi, because he was
dead when Hitler was a political leader. Maybe, Bainbridge means that Nietzsche
would have supported Hitler, had he not been dead. This judgment implies that Nietzsche’s
political views and Hitler’s are identical in most cases, but this is also incorrect:
first, Hitler was in favor of Germany dominating the world, while Nietzsche was
in favor of a unified Europe; second, Hitler was interested in military power,
while Nietzsche was interested in intellectual power and the capacity to
interpret the world and create works of art; third, Hitler was an anti-Semite,
while Nietzsche was an anti-anti-Semite. The list could be continued. However,
I wish to make some further remarks concerning Nietzsche's anti-anti-Semitism. You can find some nasty
remarks concerning Jews in Nietzsche’s writings. These, however, concern the
Jews who developed the Jewish religion, which represents the ancestor of the
Christian one. It is hard to say whether Nietzsche’s attacks on the Jews or his
attacks on the Christian religion were nastier and stronger. In any case, he
regarded both religions as life denying an Bainbridge also suggests that the
Nazis “treated him as one of their own” (2010, 45). However, even this claim is
far from the plausible, because many Nazi scholars realized that there are many
anti-German positions in Nietzsche’s writings and that he was an anti-anti-Semite.
Even though it is true that there were scholars during the Nazi regime who were
concerned with Nietzsche’s philosophy, it is false to claim that the Nazis
“treated him as one of their own,” because the estimation of Nietzsche and his
work during the Third Reich was not universally affirmative. Many Nazi
ideologists recognized that Nietzsche went against the intentions and goals of
Nazi ideology on many fundamental issues. Bainbridge’s above comment does not
say much with respect to the estimation of Nietzsche by the Nazis but it might
say something about the author’s flawed understanding of Nietzsche.5 However, Bainbridge is not the
only one who seems to favor such an inappropriate understanding of Nietzsche. The
false judgment that Nietzsche was a proto-Nazi is still held by many educated
people, and it is very difficult to eliminate widespread prejudices. Hence,
Bostrom’s attempt, in his 2001 article, to dissociate transhumanism from
Nietzsche was a reasonable one, because dissociating these two ways of thinking
is easier than getting rid of prejudices that have been around for quite some
time. Indeed, it is praiseworthy to dissociate transhumanism from any fascist
ideology, because there is no general basis that both views have in common. However,
some bioconservative thinkers, among them Habermas, attempt to identify
transhumanist views with politically problematic ones by identifying their
views with Nietzsche’s. In his influential essay on liberal eugenics, Habermas (2001,
43) talks about some freaky intellectuals who reject what they see as the
illusion of equality and try to develop a very German naturalistic ideology.
This seriously considers the potential for employing human biotechnology in the
service of Nietzschean breeding fantasies. This is the kind of identification
that Bostrom rightly fears. Habermas, who rejects all procedures of genetic enhancement,
identifies transhumanists (whom he refers to incorrectly as “posthumanists”)
with Nietzscheans, associating both with fascist breeding ideologies. Habermas
is rhetorically gifted, and he knew exactly what he was doing – that an effective
way to bring about negative reactions to human biotechnological procedures in
the reader would be to identify those measures with procedures undertaken in
Nazi Germany. This type of rhetoric is well
known in As I have shown above, it is
false to refer to Nietzsche as a Nazi. It is also false to identify
transhumanists with Nazi ideology, as Habermas does, because Nazis are in favor
of a totalitarian political organization, whereas transhumanists uphold the
value of liberal democracies. For all that, many Nietzschean philosophical
positions can be found in basic beliefs of transhumanists. Habermas agrees, but
in contrast to him I regard both philosophical approaches as stimulating,
valuable and extremely important when one deals with contemporary philosophical
and ethical challenges. Conclusion All of the issues that have
been raised above are central for the challenges we must face, given recent
biotechnological developments. Many of them touch fundamental questions about our
conception of ourselves, the world, and even the meaning of life. I very much
hope that the critical reflections I have put forward here, as a response to
papers that replied to one of my articles, will stimulate further discussions
an Notes 1. “Heritable variation –
genetic, epigenetic, behavioural, and symbolic – is the consequence both of
accidents and of instructive processes during the development” (Japlonka and Lamb
2005, 356). A striking case is that of the evolution of language: “Dor and
Japlonka see the evolution of language as the outcome of the continuous
interactions between the cultural and the genetic inheritance system” (Japlonka
and Lamb 2005, 307). 2. “Waddington’s experiments
showed that when variation is revealed by an environmental stress, selection
for an induced phenotype leads first to that phenotype being induced more
frequently, and then to its production in the absence of the inducing agent”
(Japlonka and Lamb 2005, 273). 3. Jonathan M. Levenson and J.
David Sweatt show that epigenetic mechanisms probably have an important role in
synaptic plasticity and memory formation (2005, 108-118). 4. “Belyaev’s work with silver
foxes suggested that there is a hidden genetic variation in natural populations.
This variation was reveale Bibliography Agar, N. 2004. Liberal eugenics:
In defence of human enhancement. Allhoff, F. et al. 2009.
Ethics of human enhancement – 25 questions and answers. http://www.humanenhance.com/NSF_report.pdf Andreas-Salome,
Lou. 1994. Friedrich Nietzsche in seinen
Werken. Frankfurt am Aschheim,
Steven E. 1993. The Nietzsche legacy in Bainbridge, William
Sims. 2010. Bulgarizing Nietzsche’s tomb. Journal
of Evolution and Technology 21(1) (June): 37-54. http://jetpress.org/v21/bainbridge.htm Beese, F. 2004. Was ist
Psychotherapie? Ein Leitfaden für Laien zur Information über ambulante und
stationäre Psychotherapie. Goettingen: V&R. Birx, H. J. 2006. Dynamische
Integrität. In Eugenik un Blackford, Russell.
2010. Editorial – Nietzsche and European posthumanisms. Journal of Evolution and Technology 21(1) (January):
i-iii. http://jetpress.org/v21/blackford.htm Bostrom,
N. Bostrom,
N. 2001. Tranhumanist values. Version of http://www.nickbostrom.com/tra/values.html Buddensiek, F. 2002. Hexis. In
Wörterbuch der antiken Philosophie., ed. C. Horn and C. Rapp, 189-190. München: Beck. Habermas, Jürgen. 1985. Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne:
Zwölf Vorlesungen. Frankfurt am Habermas, J. 2001. Die Zukunft der menschlichen Natur. Auf dem
Weg zu einer liberalen Eugenik? Frankfurt am Hauskeller,
Michael. 2010. Nietzsche, the overhuman, and the posthuman: A reply to Stefan
Sorgner. Journal of Evolution and
Technology 21(1) (January): 5-8. http://jetpress.org/v21/hauskeller.htm Hibbard, Bill.
2010. Nietzsche’s overhuman is an ideal. Whereas posthumans will be real. Journal of Evolution and Technology 21(1) (February):
9-12. http://jetpress.org/v21/hibbard.htm
Hughes, James. 2004. Citizen cyborg.
Why democratic societies must respond to
the redesigned human of the future. Kuhn, Thomas. 1962. The structure of scientific revolutions.
McCaffrey, A. P. et
al. 2002. RNA interference in adult mice. Nature
418 (6893): 38-39. Japlonka, E. and M. J. Lamb. 2005. Evolution
in four dimensions: Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in
the history of life. Levenson, J. M. and J. D. Sweatt. 2005. Epigenetic mechanisms in memory
formation. Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 6, 108-118. Maguire A.M., F. Simonelli, and E. A. Pierce. 2008. Safety and efficacy
of gene transfer for Leber’s congenital amaurosis. Malcolm, J. More, Max. 2010. The
overhuman in the transhuman. Journal of
Evolution and Technology 21(1) (January): 1-4. http://jetpress.org/v21/more.htm Morris, K. V. et al. 2004.
Small interfering RNA-induced transcriptional gene silencing in human cells. Science 305(5688): 1289-1292. Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1967ff.
Sämtliche Werke – Kritische
Studienausgabe in. 15 volumes. Ed. by G. Colli and M. Montinari, München/
New York: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag. (Cited in the text as “KSA”.) Rabelhofer, B. 2006. Symptom, Sexualitaet,
Trauma. Wuerzburg: K&N. Ranisch, Robert and Julian Savulescu. 2009. Ethik und Enhancement. In Der neue Mensch: enhancement und Genetik
ed. Nikolaus Knoepffeler and Julian Savulescu, 21-54. Rentrop, M., R. Müller, and J. Baeuml, eds. 2009. Klinikleitfaden Psychiatrie und Psychotherapie. Muenchen: Elsevier. Robertson, J. A. 1994. Children of choice: Freedom, and the new reproductive
technologies. Roden, David.
2010. Deconstruction and excision in philosophical posthumanism. Journal of Evolution and Technology 21(1) (June):
27-36. http://jetpress.org/v21/roden.htm Sandel, Michael J. 2007. The case
against perfection. Ethics in the age of genetic engineering. Seel, M. 1998. Die Macht des Erscheinens – Nietzsches ästhetische
Marginalisierung des Seins. DU (June):
26-28. Sloterdijk,
Peter. 1987. Kopernikanische Mobilmachung
und ptolemäische Abrüstung: Ästhetischer Versuch. Frankfurt am Song, E. et al. 2003. RNA
interference targeting Fas protects mice from fulminant hepatitis. Nature Medicine 9 (3): 347-51. Sorgner, Stefan
Lorenz. 2010. Menschenwürde nach Nietzsche. Die Geschichte
eines Begriffs. Sorgner, Stefan
Lorenz. 2007. Metaphysics without truth: On
the importance of consistency within Nietzsche’s philosophy. Rev. second ed. Sorgner, Stefan
Lorenz. 2000. Nietzsche and Sorgner, Stefan
Lorenz. 2009b. Nietzsche and Heraclitus. In The Encyclopedia of Time: Science, Philosophy, Theology, and Culture,
ed. H. James Birx, Vol. 2, 919-22. Sorgner, Stefan Lorenz.
2009. Nietzsche, the overhuman and transhumanism. Journal
of Evolution and Technology 20(1) (March) 2009: 29-42. http://jetpress.org/v20/sorgner.htm Sorgner, Stefan
Lorenz. 2004. Vattimo, Metaphysik un Stambler, Ilia. 2010. Life extension
– a conservative enterprise? Some fin-de-siècle and early twentieth
century precursors of transhumanism. Journal of Evolution and Technology 21(1)
(March): 13-26. http://jetpress.org/v21/stambler.htm Varela, Francisco J., Evans Thompson,
and Eleanor Rosch. 1991. The embodied mind:
Cognitive science and human experience. Vattimo, Gianni. 1988. The end of modernity: Nihilism and hermeneutics
in post-modern culture. Trans. Jon R. Snyder. Yovel, Y. 1994. Nietzsche, the
Jews, and ressentimen |