The
Pleasure Principle as a Tool for Scientific Forecasting of Human Self-Evolution
Victor Yu. Argonov
Pacific Oceanological Institute of the Russian
Academy of Sciences Journal of Evolution and Technology -
Vol. 24 Issue 2 – August 2014 - pgs 63-78 Abstract
The pleasure
principle (PP) may be a verifiable fundamental law of the living matter in the
universe, and this law might then be used for forecasting human self-evolution.
I do not pretend to “prove” PP, but argue that it must be regarded as a
scientific hypothesis. Accordingly, I formulate verifiable and falsifiable
postulates of PP. Their confirmation would allow the construction of a new
scientific discipline, hedodynamics, that would be able to forecast the future
development of human civilization and even the probable structure and
psychology of other rational beings within the universe. I suggest basic
hedodynamical scenarios for human (posthuman) civilization and argue that the
discovery of the neural correlate of pleasure would provide more detailed
forecasts. In particular, I demonstrate how the studies of pleasure mechanisms
might predict the degree of aggression in future societies. I conclude that PP
may become a scientific basis for fundamental, not phenomenological (based on
extrapolations), future forecasting on large timescales. 1. Introduction Transhumanist philosophers argue that the most important future changes
in human civilization will be related to human self-evolution (modification of
human biology by technological means). Contemporary humanity modifies mostly
its environment, while future humans will increasingly have opportunities to
modify their own bodies: to increase lifespan, intellect, physical strength,
etc. (see Bostrom 2005 and references at provided in Wikipedia’s article on
Transhumanism).1 This view is shared by a rapidly increasing number
of people, but the most problematic issue relates to the prospect of radical
changes in human psychology (in particular, our motivations). In popular
culture, this has mostly been considered in the dystopian tradition of Aldous
Huxley’s Brave New World (1932). It
is often implicitly supposed that radical modification of psychology is too
dangerous for human civilization. In my view, however, it is inevitable.
Moreover, the process has already begun. In modern society, education, propaganda, hypnosis, advertising,
psychoactive drugs, etc., are already available to manipulate (reprogram) our
motivations in a sophisticated manner. Nonetheless, today’s technologies have many limitations. For
example, they cannot be employed to make deliberate changes to a person’s
preferences in art or sex, and there are no effective methods to motivate
humans to perform hard work without offering some economic advantage or
threatening violence. However, we can safely suppose that in the future novel
methods of artificial stimulation of pleasure (including complete elimination
of human suffering without damage to health; see Pearce 2005) and reprogramming
of motivations will allow any human to get pleasure from physical
labor, vigorous activity, scientific research, the creative arts, and even the
experience of pain (Argonov 2008; Kosarev 1997). Motivations establish the goals of human activity, while our
technologies provide only tools to help achieve them. Therefore, self-evolution
of human motivations is a key to the self-evolution of humankind. And in this
paper I argue that the trajectory of self-evolution is predictable: human
beings will change their motivations in accordance with the pleasure
principle (PP). Thus, I
will criticize today’s dominant view that PP is merely a speculative
philosophical doctrine, and will show that it might provide a unique scientific
basis for fundamental forecasting of the distant future of human society, and
even of interactions between different civilizations in the universe. In
particular, I will show that an advanced neuroscience of pleasure and
motivation mechanisms might predict the degree of aggression in self-evolving
civilizations. 2. Glossary: basic terms and values Subjective phenomena is a general
term describing anything that is subjectively felt/perceived by a sentient
creature: i.e., sensations, emotions, perception of time, feeling of pleasure,
thoughts, and volitional acts. Consciousness (phenomenal consciousness, subjective
reality, mind) is the totality of all subjective phenomena of a
single creature. Note that in this paper, I use the word “consciousness” as a synonym of
subjective reality. Therefore, in principle, even primitive animals may be
conscious (or sentient). In this paper, “consciousness” is distinguished from
“intellect” and other complex human activity. Volitional behavior is behavior that is
subjectively perceived by the creature as its “own deliberate actions,” taking
place by its “own choice” or upon its “own decision.” A neural
correlate of a subjective phenomenon is a physical (physiological) phenomenon that
is unambiguously related to the subjective phenomenon and contains complete
information about it. Neural correlates of subjective phenomena are the objective
phenomena, the study of which provides knowledge of the subjective reality of
another being: perception, dreams, hallucinations, emotions, and the feeling of
pleasure, etc. Materialism is the doctrine that each
subjective phenomenon has a neural correlate and that matter contains
comprehensive information about consciousness (including information that some
particular organism is conscious). Note that neural correlates of some
subjective phenomena are still hypothetical. The search for the neural correlates
is a crucial branch of today’s experimental studies of consciousness (Metzinger
2000). Pleasure (happiness, hedonic tone)
p is a measure of a creature’s subjective satisfaction with the current
state of its consciousness regardless of the specific factors that have caused
it: the measure of desirability of this state. Hedonic tone may be negative
(suffering) or positive (pleasure per se). Comfort q is a hypothetical
physiological parameter, unambiguously determining a creature’s volitional behavior
according to Postulates 1 and 4, and being a neural correlate of pleasure p
according to Postulate 2 (see Section 3.3). The pleasure principle (PP) is the hypothesis
that volitional behavior is always related to the maximization of pleasure p,
or, at least, the avoidance of its negative values. Rigorous reformulation of
PP is given in Section 3.3. Planning and forecasting time T is a period of time
during which an organism is able to predict the dynamics of q and plan
its volitional behavior. Lifespan Tmax is the lifespan of
a living organism, the maximal possible value of the planning and forecasting
time T. Utility Q is the “integral pleasure”: a
product of planning and forecasting time T and average expected comfort
q
during this time:2 Hedodynamics is a quantitative theory of
individual behavior and societal development based on the pleasure principle. Evolutionary programming of motivations (EPM) is an evolutionary
mechanism that determines which stimuli an animal feels as pleasant and which
as unpleasant. Self-evolution is the artificial and
purposeful self-modification of rational organisms with the use of technology
(affecting intellect, physical abilities of the body, lifespan, motivations,
etc.). Artificial programming of motivations (APM) is an artificial
and purposeful regulation that determines which stimuli an organism feels as
pleasant and which as unpleasant (by means of propaganda, psychological
technologies, chemical and surgical invasion in brain). 3. The pleasure principle as a scientific hypothesis 3.1 Historical overview One of the most problematic questions in the history
of human civilization is the existence of the universal motivational mechanism,
which is common to all animals and underlies all particular manifestations of
volitional behavior. The first hedonistic conception that (1) a human
being has a common motivational mechanism throughout their life and (2) this mechanism is based on a
striving for pleasure (happiness) dates back as far as to Aristippos of Cyrene,
a student of Socrates. Later in classical antiquity, the idea was developed by
Epicurus and his followers, and in modern times, interest in the problem
increased after works by the major British utilitarians (Bentham 1789;
Mill 1863). Jeremy Bentham argued that (theoretically) any good is a measurable
value and any human ideas about good and evil are based on the subjective
experience of pleasant and unpleasant feelings. On this approach, other
rational foundations of ethics are impossible. When deprived of the feeling of
pleasure and suffering, a human being cannot have motivations; he or she will
be unable to distinguish between good and evil, and will not praise or value
even his or her own life. Utilitarian philosophers distinguish ethical
hedonism (utilitarianism per se,
in which pleasure is the sole ethical value), psychological hedonism
(pleasure is the sole goal of activity), and physiological hedonism
(pleasure is the sole goal of activity, and it has purely physiological basis).
In this paper, I consider only physiological hedonism (and use the term
“pleasure principle,” PP, for it). In the nineteenth century, hedonistic philosophy gave
an impetus to the development of social science and economic theory (Gossen 1854; Jevons 1871;
Menger 1871; Walras 1874; Edgeworth 1881). PP was also accepted and
popularized by the famous psychologists Gustav Fechner (1873) and Sigmund Freud
(1920). The discovery of the limbic system’s pleasure centers, and experiments
on their electric stimulation (Olds and Milner 1954; Delgado 1965; Sem-Jacobsen
and Styri 1972), gave further support to the idea that the distinction of
pleasant and unpleasant feelings and emotions is a fundamental property of all
higher animals. However, the idea that all their motivations are based on
pleasure (i.e., that the level of pleasure is a universal meta-motivation) did
not obtain the status of a true scientific theory. Significant numbers of
researchers still reject PP as an unscientific, senseless, useless, or
unverifiable idea. In this paper, however, I propose to demonstrate that
they are wrong. I will reformulate the PP as a group of postulates, each of
which is amenable to scientific validation. I will then show that positive
verification of PP postulates would provide the basis of a new scientific
domain, hedodynamics, with powerful predictive abilities in some fields. 3.2 Requirements for the scientific formulation of the
pleasure principle Let us discuss typical conceptual problems relating to PP and outline
the conditions for its true scientific formulation. Condition 1: non-tautology. PP
should not be justified only by definitions. It should admit of a formal
logical possibility of being either true or false. In the relevant literature, pleasure is
often defined in a purely behaviorist manner. For example, Simonov (1966, 1986)
has defined a positive emotion as an emotion that an animal “wants to
strengthen, elongate, and repeat,” while negative emotion is emotion that “he
strives to weaken, interrupt, and prevent.” This, however, does not say
anything regarding the behavior. It solely offers a terminology to describe the
behavior. Bertrand Russell (1946) was one of the famous critics of the pleasure
principle as a mere truism. The definition “pleasure is that which the animal
strives for” automatically proves the statement “the animal always strives for
pleasure.” In order to overcome the problem, we can distinguish three phenomena
(see Section 2): subjective feelings of pleasure (“pleasure”); objective
neural conditions that produce pleasure (“comfort”); and objective
behavior maintaining these conditions. Scientific study can then detect any
correlation between these phenomena. It will be empirically demonstrable, not
merely an artifact of the conceptual apparatus we are using. Condition 2: objectivity. PP should be
scientifically verifiable or falsifiable. Therefore, it should be
related to objective phenomena. Behaviorist definitions of
pleasure use objective terminology, but they lead to tautology. Therefore, we
must regard pleasure as a subjective phenomenon, even though this leads to the
problem of measurement. PP states that volitional action maximizes pleasure.
Both volition and pleasure are subjective phenomena. How are we to detect them
in an objective study? In order to overcome the problem of subjectivity, in
Section 3.3 I set out two meta-postulates that pleasure and volition have
neural correlates. Rigorous verification of these meta-postulates is
problematic, but they are in a good agreement with modern trends (Metzinger
2000). Condition 3: practical
significance. The theory built on the postulates of PP (hedodynamics) must have
some advantages when compared with the existing theories. A new theory’s predictions
must be more universal, more precise, or more easily obtained in technical
terms than the predictions made by the existing psychology, evolution theory or
neurophysiology. In Section 4, I will show that there is at least one field
where PP might be a crucial predictive tool: self-evolution of humans
and other hypothetical rational beings in the universe. 3.3 Postulates of the pleasure principle and
hedodynamics Meta-postulate 1. Pleasure may be
measured in the objective study of the brain (pleasure has a neural correlate). Meta-postulate 2. Conscious
(volitional) and unconscious behavior may be distinguished in the objective
study of the brain. General verification of Meta-postulates 1 and 2 is a hard
interdisciplinary problem. They are definitely true in materialism, but
the verification of materialism is also a hard problem. In practice, however,
these postulates are implicitly assumed in most modern studies of pleasure
mechanisms. In many particular experiments, verbal reports of participants may
be enough to establish the correspondence between subjective and objective
phenomena. Rigorously speaking, PP is a scientific hypothesis if its
meta-postulates are true. Otherwise, the condition of objectivism (from Section
3.2) is not fulfilled, so PP is scientifically unverifiable. Now let us introduce the postulates that are specifically related to PP
(they are definitely verifiable, if the meta-postulates are true). Postulate 1: the existence
of q. Any volitional actions of a conscious organism are
determined by a single physiological parameter q (comfort), which may take
negative and positive values. In its behavior, an organism either (1) strives
to maximize the current value of q, or (2) only avoids negative
current values of q (the particular option is to be determined by
experiments). The first option is Freud’s
conventional “pleasure principle” (Freud 1920). The second is his early
“unpleasure principle” (1899) or negative hedonism. According to
the second option, if q falls below zero, then the organism changes its
behavior, but if the value of q is positive, then the organism ignores
more comfortable choices (compare Voltaire’s “the best is the enemy of the
good”). Postulate 1 can be interpreted as the existence of fundamental
meta-motivation, which cannot be reprogrammed by any modification of a
creature’s brain. Postulate 2: the correlation
between q and p. Comfort q is a neural correlate of pleasure.
Negative values of q correspond to suffering and negative emotions (p < 0),
while positive values of q correspond to pleasure per se and positive emotions
(p > 0). I have stated Postulate 2
separately because one can theoretically imagine the alternative situation that
the behavior is regulated by a single parameter (Postulate 1 is true), but this
parameter does not correspond to pleasure (Postulate 2 is false). Postulate 3: the universality
of q. Comfort has a similar physiological nature in all possible conscious
creatures. At first glance, this
postulate seems to be too strong. However, it is based, at least in
materialism, on very simple philosophical considerations. Let us presume that
materialism is true. Hence, matter contains full information about any
subjective phenomenon of any conscious creature. One might nevertheless assume
that the neural correlates of pleasure are significantly different in different
organisms. For example, in one animal, pleasure might be determined by the
concentration of dopamine, while in another it might be determined by the
concentration of opioids. These two values cannot be reduced to the common
scale. However, the feeling of pleasure is similar in both animals. Therefore,
at least one subjective fact (the fact of the similarity of feelings) is not
manifested in objective reality. This runs counter to materialism. In other words,
Postulate 3 can be proved logically in materialism. We consider it to be a
postulate only because we do not know whether materialism (as defined) is true. Fig. 1.
Real and forecasted dynamics of dog’s comfort. Dog, being in a neutral mood (q
= 0), sees the food. Predicted future q is positive, so the positive
emotion develops. Then, dog sees the unpredicted factor: food is guarded by the
man with a rod. Predicted future q goes negative, so dog feels fear
(which is a negative emotion). Dog corrects behavior and runs away, so fear
disappears Postulate 4: the correlation
between q and Q. Intellect considers the maximization of
utility Q (see definition and formula (1) in Section 2) as a dominating goal.
There is a positive correlation between the predicted value of Q and the
current value of q. This stimulates an animal to maximize Q. In other words, anticipation
of pleasure in the future causes positive emotion right now, while the negative
prognosis causes negative emotion. The value of q is a cause of activity
(Fechner 1873) and the value of Q is a goal. Postulate 4 is equivalent to
Freud’s “reality principle” (Freud 1920). Let us illustrate its action
by a typical behavioral example. A dog approaches food and sees a man with a
rod near it (Fig. 1). The dog thinks that the man might attack it, and the
averaged expected comfort q (as well as Q) in the near-term
future is negative. To prevent this outcome, the dog’s brain develops the
negative emotion of fear. As a result, current q also turns negative and
the dog runs away. The existence of such a stimulation mechanism is obvious. It
should be noted, however, that Postulate 4 is a stronger statement. It not only
declares the possibility of correlation between q and Q but also
directly relates it to intellect. Postulate 4 is especially important in the
study of human beings, because their planning and forecasting time T is
comparable with their lifespan Tmax. Therefore, if
Postulate 4 is true, then at least some humans strive for survival not only because
of the instinctive fear of death, but also because they strive for the
maximization of Q (if average expected q is positive).
Suppression of instincts (by totalitarian propaganda or by technical methods)
can’t eliminate this factor. According to Postulate 4, only suppression of
human comfort or intellect might force an individual human being to sacrifice
his life for “great ideas.” 3.4. Hypotheses relating to the neural correlate of
pleasure: overview Rigorous verification of PP postulates can become possible only after the discovery of the neural correlate of pleasure that has been intensively searched for since the mid-twentieth century. In this section, I will give a short overview of discovered mechanisms and declared hypotheses. Most of authors relate pleasure to particular neurochemical processes.
Earlier neurochemical theories, formed in the mid-twentieth century, related
pleasure to the action of cathecholamines (such as dopamine and noradrenaline)
that regulate the passage of signals in the neural network. Famous experiments
by James Olds, Peter Milner and others (Olds and Milner 1954; Delgado 1965)
showed that electrical stimulation of some brain regions (responsible for the
production of catecholamines) radically changes an animal’s behavior: the
animal feels an overwhelming motivation to continue stimulation infinitely. It
was hypothesized that animals feel strong pleasure. Therefore, the relevant
brain regions were called “pleasure centers.” However, further experiments on humans have shown that neither their
stimulation (Sem-Jacobsen and Styri 1972) nor the use of dopaminergic drugs
produces rather strong pleasure. They produce obvious stimulation effects, but
their hedonic effect seems to be a rather mistaken interpretation (Berridge and
Robinson 1998). Catecholamines are probably responsible not for pleasure but
for the estimation of its future value (Schultz et al. 1997, Borgkvist et
al. 2007). Today, many authors suggest that not catecholamines but opioids
must be regarded as a “real substance of pleasure.” Using opiate drugs, humans
feel pleasure that is much stronger than was reported in old “pleasure center”
stimulation experiments. New experiments (Borgkvist et al. 2007) have shown
that opioids influence mice even after “switching off” major dopamine
mechanisms. Kent Berridge discovered two small hedonic “hotspots” in a
cubic millimeter of the rostrodorsal region of the medial shell of the nucleus
accumbens and in the ventral pallidum (Kringelbach and Berridge
2006; Smith and Berridge 2007) and showed that they produce much more clear
hedonistic effect than Olds’s “pleasure centers”. He hypothesizes that opioid m-receptors in these
“hotspots” might be real “receptors of pleasure” of the brain. Neurochemical theories of pleasure have one serious drawback: they do
not clarify the particular physiological parameter that might be unambiguously
related to pleasure. There is always a chain of effects (generation of
substances, their action on receptors, intracellular processes, regulation of
signal propagation), and it is unknown which of them “really produces”
pleasure. In response to this problem, some authors have suggested more
fundamental hypotheses. Karl Friston (2010) states that an animal always strives to maximize the
predictability of its environment. The degree of predictability is estimated by
computing the information analogue of free energy, a thermodynamic
parameter introduced by Hermann von Helmholtz. According to Friston’s theory,
the brain estimates the value of informational free energy (in particular, for
sensory data) and tries to minimize it in order to increase predictability.
Note that informational free energy is not physical free energy (which is
related to metabolism and usually maximized, not minimized, by living
organisms). A recent study (Friston et al. 2010) has shown that the level of
dopamine might also be related to sensory prediction error and free energy. Several authors relate pleasure to intracellular processes. This view
matches well with modern tendencies to depart from old ideas of the neuron as a
“mere trigger.” Many contemporary works characterize the neuron as a small but
independent organism with its own memory and computing power (Koch and Segev
2000) or even individual consciousness (Edwards 2005; Sevush 2006). Soviet
scientists Vladimir Shvyrkov (1995) and Yury Alexandrov (1999) developed a
theory that each neuron has its own genetically preset motivations,
demanding saturation with particular
metabolites. Each neuron “wants” these substances and generates signals until
other cells provide them. Cells that are not able to take required metabolites
commit apoptosis (Alexandrov 1999), which is an analogue of suicide motivated
by the absence of joy of life. It might be hypothesized that human pleasure is a sense of “satiety” of
an individual’s neurons. Sergey Murik (2006) suggests an alternative hypothesis
that q is related not to cell metabolism but to cellular membrane
polarization (its static level). Normally, the in-cell medium has a
negative charge. As a result, there is a polarization between the intracellular
and external medium (of the order of –70 mV). The level of static polarization
in animal and plant cells is related to the favorability of their metabolic
condition. Decreased polarization (depolarization) indicates the
presence of negative factors (Blake et al. 1988;
Pyatygin et al. 2006). In normal conditions, in neurons, depolarization
causes signal generation (Fig. 2a), and polarization restores to the normal or
increased level (hyperpolarization). If an unpleasant factor presents
too long, the cell spends all its energy, becomes exhausted and decays. Murik
associates hyperpolarization directly with pleasant emotions, and
depolarization with unpleasant emotions. This idea maps with the results of
experiments showing a correlation between: (1) negative emotional behavior and
brain polarization with electrodes (Murik 1996); (2) neural depolarization and
phantom-limb pain (Wu et al. 2005) (Fig. 2b); and,
(3) neural hyperpolarization and the effects of opiates (Duan et al. 1990;
Chieng and Christie 1994). Fig. 2. .
Electric processes in neurons and their hypothetical hedonistic interpretation: (a) generation of action potential as a reaction to membrane depolarization (unpleasant factor?); (b) prolonged membrane depolarization due to phantom limb pain (Wu et. al. 2005) Today, the search for a neural correlate of pleasure continues, and
there is no universally accepted theory. We have some methods of chemical
control of both the feeling of comfort (with opioids and some other drugs) and
the feeling of anticipated utility (with dopamine drugs) in mammals, but we
have not indentified the detailed underlying mechanisms of these effects.
However, the most realistic assumption is that the fundamental neural correlate
of pleasure is somehow related to a creature’s survival at cellular or physical
level. Most likely, pleasure is a kind of indicator of the fundamental
“vitality” of a neural system (expressed in terms of cellular membrane
polarization, cell nutrition, or thermodynamic parameters). 4. Self-evolutionary applications of hedodynamics In this section, I will outline the basic evolutionary and
self-evolutionary predictions of PP (assuming that it is a true principle). Let
us presume that the PP postulates identified above (Section 3.3) are true and
discuss their consequences. 4.1 Hedodynamics and biological evolution Generalizing several hypotheses from Section 3.4, we can base our
analysis on the assumption that q is a microscopic indicator of a
system’s vitality, and, at least for simple organisms, that it is closely
related to their ability to survive in the nearest future. Most primitive
organisms only maximize q or maintain it at the non-negative level (T=0).
For example, the organism might be stimulated by a deficiency of nutrients and
stop acting when their normal level is restored (Fig. 3 shows typical behavior
of bacteria depending on nutrient concentration). Since we do not know whether
these organisms have subjective feelings, this might not be PP in a rigorous
sense; it is, however, at least its basic physiological analogue (and some
authors do suppose that each cell literally has subjective feelings (Edwards
2005; Sevush 2006)). Such behavior is primitive: it is based on a single
motivation that is always the same (See Fig. 4a and Table 1). It is not optimal
for survival of the individual or population. Fig. 3. Radical
change in typical bacterial motion due to hunger: (a), (b) when the environment
contains nutrients, bacterium moves along random trajectory and the frequency
of its random turns depends on the satiety (pleasure?); (c) when no nutrients available,
bacterium goes hungry and begin to move in a constant direction in order to
find food (restore pleasure?) as quickly as possible Accordingly, animals with complex neural systems display more complex
behavior. They have numerous motivations other than nutrition: avoiding danger,
accumulation of food supplies, building nests, sexual behavior, etc. They are
able to feel pleasure and displeasure in the absence of factors that are
important for primitive organisms. How did this become possible? According to Shvyrkov (1995) and
Alexandrov (1999), it might be supposed that cells, because of certain
mutations, require new sorts of metabolites that were not vital for ancient
predecessors; therefore, the motivations of the whole organism change. A simpler
alternative is that other processes in higher animals “deceive” consciousness,
depriving some neurons of nutrients in order to achieve their activity. Today,
exact microscopic motivational mechanisms are unknown, but, anyway, complex
organisms are able to feel pleasure and displeasure from factors that are not
directly related to their nutrition and/or survival in a short timeframe (see
Fig. 4b and Table 1). Therefore, during the process of biological evolution,
numerous programmable motivations replaced a single
non-programmable motivation. Evolutionary programming of
motivations (EPM) (see Section 2 for definition) became possible. Fig. 4.
Hypothetical evolution of pleasure mechanisms (assuming sentience of primitive
creatures): (a) in primitive creatures, pleasure encodes some factor, important
for life (for example, satiety); the goal of behavior is pleasure; (b) in
higher animals, EPM-based stimulus analyzer determines which stimuli should be
interpreted as negative or positive pleasure (suggesting behavior programs
rewarded by pleasure); behavior is a “hunt” for particular pleasant factors
suggested by analyzer; (c) in self-evolving humans, stimulus analyzer may be
reprogrammed artificially, therefore, it may be considered as a part of
modifiable environment, and schemes (a) and (c) are equivalent; the goal of
behavior is pleasure itself, not particular pleasant factors. See also Table 1 What might hedodynamics say about the evolution of motivations and the
structure of particular organisms in wild nature? It might say almost nothing.
Primitive creatures can be described by their striving for maximization of some
vital parameter (such as amount of nutrients), and the term “comfort” would be
just another word for the same thing. In higher animals, multiple motivations
emerge, but they are subordinate to natural selection. In the framework of EPM, PP is not an independent factor; it just
“serves” evolutionary “needs.” It follows that hedodynamics would add nothing to existing theory of evolution. However,
the situation changes radically when we consider the development of rational
beings. 4.2 Hedodynamics and self-evolution of rational beings As a result of their highly developed intellects, humans have specific
behavioral features that were impossible in earlier animals. Let us outline two
of them. First, the human horizon of forecasting and planning T is
comparable with the individual lifespan Tmax. As a result,
humans (according to Postulate 4) try to prolong life as long as average
comfort is positive (or commit suicide, if it is negative). Second, the
appearance of technological progress radically changes the environment and
begins to change the organism itself: i.e. self-evolution begins, one
of the trends of which is the artificial
programming of motivations (APM) (see Section 2 for definition). Non-human animals act according to existing motivations, but do not try
to change them. Humans act according to existing motivations, but also think
about their “goodness” (one of the characteristic human motivations is to think
about motivations). Human beings typically criticize some motivations as
dangerous, egoistic, bad for health, etc. Modern society uses propaganda,
education, drugs, and other tools to modify human motivations in a desired
manner. Today’s methods of APM have serious limitations (as touched upon in the
Introduction), but they are developing rapidly. In the future, the emergence of
new powerful APM methods seems inevitable. While today’s APM methods are based
mostly on socio-psychological manipulation, future APM may be based on direct
stimulation or modification of the brain. One simple approach to radical APM is surgical correction or destruction
of certain brain centers. Such possibilities have been reported in many
experiments with animals and humans. Early experiments were related to
macroscopic brain invasion accompanied by multi-aspect changes in behavior. For
example (in Kluever and Bucy 1938), bilateral
removal of the amygdala and hippocampus in rhesus monkeys changed some of their
preferences (specifically, they ceased to fear snakes), but these effects were
accompanied by general brain disorders. In the second half of the
twentieth century, more precise (and less destructive) methods were developed.
Some of them are used today for surgical treatment of drug addiction
(Kringelbach and Berridge 2006). However, these methods are also destructive.
In future, a much more universal (and non-destructive) APM approach might be
provided by wearable and programmable machines that observe human activity and
stimulate pleasure (electrically, chemically, or by more sophisticated and less
invasive methods) in desired situations (Argonov 2008; Kosarev 1997). For
example, a machine might be programmed to stimulate pleasure every time an
individual does physical exercises or studies for a university examination.
Today, this APM approach is limited by two factors: (1) electronic devices are
able to distinguish only the simplest patterns of human behavior and life
situations; (2) absolutely safe pleasure stimulation is still a problem. The
first limitation seems to be purely technical. The second is caused by our lack
of knowledge of pleasure mechanisms. Therefore, both limitations seem to be
temporary. In the future, there will be almost unlimited possibilities. Once developed, universal APM techniques will radically change
humankind. New APM methods might be the object of ethical criticism and social
conflicts, but it seems almost impossible to prohibit them totally. It should
be noted that some contemporary APM methods (such as surgical treatment of drug
addiction) also attract ethical controversy, yet they are used in practice.
After the emergence of radical APM methods, many novel social problems might
appear. In particular, some people might try to use permanent pleasure
stimulation (therefore, they will have no motivations for any activity). On the
other hand, some authorities might try to force people to program themselves in
a specific manner, thus building an “ideal” totalitarian society (these
problems and their likely solutions are discussed in detail in Argonov 2008).
Anyway, as a rule, according to Postulate 4, rational people will try to modify
themselves in the following two directions: Direction 1. Maximization
of lifespan Tmax (modification of body in
order to raise its reliability, eliminate dangerous motivations, and construct
useful motivations). Direction 2. Maximization
of average comfort
q
(modification of brain in order
to increase maximal possible level of pleasure and stimulation of pleasure in
already available range). In both liberal and totalitarian societies, there would be at least some
people with enough political power to follow this optimal strategy (in
agreement or in conflict with other parts of society that might be forced to
choose non-optimal motivations). And this would radically change civilizational
development. With advanced forms of APM, human beings will obtain the opportunity to
control q directly, much like primitive organisms (compare Figs. 4a and
c). Therefore, pleasure will increasingly become the dominating factor in human
development, and hedodynamics will turn into a powerful prognostic tool. More
detailed scenarios of development depend on the nature of the neural correlate
of pleasure (unknown today). In particular, the nature of this correlate might
determine the degree of aggression in self-evolving societies. Let us examine
two basic scenarios. 4.3 Basic hedodynamical scenarios of civilization
development Once human civilization is completely transformed,
becoming a self-evolving system (i.e. when its development depends mostly on
natural resources and politics, rather than on technological limitations), the
most likely scenario for further development depends strongly on the nature of
the neural correlate of pleasure. In particular, the most important unknown
factor is the existence, or otherwise, of fundamental limits of pleasure. There
are two major alternatives: Alternative 1. Non-local
mechanisms of pleasure. Comfort q is determined by the integral material
values (volume, mass, energy, electric charge, etc.). For example, q
might be determined by the total amount of opioids or nutrients in brain.
Therefore, comfort q can be maximized nearly infinitely via technical methods
(with the consumption of resources and/or the increase of the body), and the extensive
scenario for civilization is probable. Alternative 2. Local
mechanisms of pleasure. Comfort q is determined by the average (differential)
material values (density, concentration, frequency, etc.). For example, q might
be determined by the concentration of opioids or nutrients, or by the rate of
computations. Therefore, comfort q might have some natural limits, and
the intensive scenario for civilization is probable. Extensive scenario. If comfort q is
determined by integral, summed-up factors, the increase of the maximum level of
comfort q requires accumulation of resources (in particular, an increase
in the mass and volume of the organism). If the human is able to have more
intense pleasure than the mouse, then the further maximization of body size
might be preferable. An individual who has accumulated more resources can
become happier, and this factor might induce violent conflicts (more violent
than those induced by money or natural resources in the modern world). Some
individuals might achieve social agreement for the sake of security; however,
the global trend will be the decay of human populations, accompanied by growth
in the individual power of the remaining people. If individuals are able to
merge their consciousnesses without the destruction of each other, then an
expansion can take place without conflicts. In the far future, super-organisms
like Solaris Ocean (Lem 1961) or Utilitronium (Pearce 2014) might appear, and
the total division of all available matter and/or energy in the universe among
cosmic individuals is a plausible scenario. In any event, the long-term
self-evolutionary dynamics will involve two parameters (because both Tmax and
q
remain variables). Intensive scenario. If comfort q is
determined by average characteristics such as energy density, concentrations of
substances, rate of computations per unit of volume, etc., then, at early
periods of self-evolution, humans will try to increase average q. Sooner or later, however, in
agreement with contemporary physics, q will reach saturation. Any
further increase of
q
will be impossible or
unprofitable for the maximization of Q. Hence, according to Postulate 4,
humans will try to maximize only a single parameter, lifespan Tmax (civilization returns to the one-parameter strategy, similar to that
realized in the process of biological evolution). Elsewhere (Argonov 2008), I
have discussed the situation in detail,
arguing that the most anti-utopian political systems must be unstable. Typical
individuals will subordinate all other motivations to their own survival. In the intensive scenario, conflicts for resources would not be so
prominent as in the extensive scenario, because their accumulation would not
guarantee a proportional lifespan increase (while conflict itself might
decrease it). Humans (feeling maximal happiness almost all the time) would need
no specific entertainments. Most likely, they would program themselves for
peaceful activities related to medicine, security, energy production, and so
on.
Table 1. Hedodynamical periodization of the
evolution. Here q is comfort of an organism;
q
is its
average value during life; Tmax is lifespan; and Q is utility (see Section 2 for details) 5. Conclusion In this paper, I have shown that the pleasure principle (PP)
might be not only a fundamental, verifiable law of the universe, but also a
unique predictive tool for the distant future of humankind. Today’s forecasts
are based mostly on extrapolations of global trends (“macroscopic,” or “phenomenological,” methods). Such methods demonstrate
good results in many fields from demography to computer science, but all of
them are applicable to the near future
only. Forecasting of civilizational development over centuries and millennia is
impossible without alternative methods that might be called “microscopic,”
or “fundamental.”
Such methods must be based on fundamental laws of civilizational development.
In this paper, I have argued that PP might be such a law. I have proposed a group of PP postulates, each of which requires
scientific validation (and is formulated to acknowledge that need in
principle). The cornerstone of PP is pleasure’s neural correlate, a
physiological parameter having a one-to-one correspondence with the level of
pleasure subjectively experienced by the creature concerned. The discovery of
this parameter, and with it confirmation of PP postulates, would lead to the
establishment of a new quantitative theory, called “hedodynamics.” PP might be especially useful for
describing the behavior of rational beings, whereas in wildlife it is
subordinate to natural selection and, thus, does not add anything new to our
knowledge. When a civilization of rational beings develops technologies of
purposeful modification of their biology (enters the stage of self-evolution),
hedodynamics becomes a useful forecasting tool, able to predict not only the
psychology of new creatures, but also their structure and the global tendencies
of their civilization’s development. In the future, detailed scientific knowledge of fundamental pleasure
mechanisms (common for humans and animals) may be used for the construction of
detailed forecasts. In particular, it may become possible to determine, whether
the future self-evolutionary scenario is extensive (unlimited aggressive
increase of bodies of individuals) or intensive (peaceful activity aimed at
lifespan extension). These surprising applications of neuroscientific knowledge
illustrate the extreme importance of interdisciplinary studies in modern
science. Notes 1. See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Transhumanism
(last accessed June 14, 2014). Like all Wikipedia articles, this undergoes a
process of continual editing. 2. In this paper, I neglect the difference between objective and
subjective time (considering t as objective time). However, in practice,
the subjective time rate g = dt / dt (a ratio between the “speeds” of
subjective and objective times) is not a constant. The value of g may be determined by some periodic neural processes,
for example, by gamma synchrony (Crick 1994). During sleep, g decreases, while during intense action it increases.
Drugs may also change the value of g. In order to generalize our approach to the case of variable subjective
time rates, Postulate 2 must be reformulated as follows: “Physiological
comfort q is a neural correlate of the product of the pleasure p and the
subjective time rate g. That is: q = gp.” Other postulates may remain unchanged, because g has a positive
value. References Alexandrov, Yu. I. 1999.
Psychophysiological regularities
of the dynamics of individual experience and the “stream of consciousness.” In Neuronal
bases and psychological aspects of consciousness, ed. C. Teddei-Ferretti
and C. Musio, 201–235. Singapore, N.Y., London, and Hong-Kong: World
Scientific. Argonov, V. 2008. Artificial
programming of human motivations: A way to degradation or rapid development? Questions
of Philosophy (in Russian) 12: 22–37. Available online http://transhumanism-russia.ru/content/view/392/144
(accessed June 6, 2014). Bentham, J. 1789. An
introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. London: T. Payne. Berridge, K. C. and T. E. Robinson. 1998. What is the role of dopamine
in reward: Hedonic impact, reward learning, or incentive salience? Brain
Research Reviews 28: 309–369. Blake, K., W. T. Clusin, M. R. Franz, and N. A. Smith. 1988. Mechanism
of depolarization in the ischaemic dog heart: Discrepancy between T-Q
potentials and potassium accumulation. Journal
of Physiology-London 397: 307–330. Borgkvist, A., A. Usiello, P. Greengard, and G. Fisone. 2007. Activation
of the cAMP/PKA/DARPP-32 signaling pathway is required for morphine psychomotor
stimulation but not for morphine reward. Neuropsychopharmacology 32:
1995–2003. Bostrom, N. 2005. A history of
transhumanist thought. Journal of Evolution and Technology 14(3): 1–25.
Available online http://jetpress.org/volume14/bostrom.html
(accessed June 9, 2014). Chieng, B. and M. J. Christie.
1994. Hyperpolarization by opioids acting on mu-receptors of a sub-population
of rat periaqueductal gray neurones in vitro. British Journal of Pharmacology 113:
121–128. Crick, F. 1994. The astonishing
hypothesis: The scientific search for the soul. New York: Charles
Scribner’s Sons. Delgado, J. M. R. 1965. Evolution of physical control of the brain.
New York: American Museum of Natural History. Duan, Sh. Zh., N. Shimizu, A.
Fukuda, T. Hori, and Y. Oomura. 1990. Hyperpolarizing action of enkephalin on
neurons in the dorsal motor nucleus of the vagus, in vitro. Brain Research
Bulletin 25: 551–559. Edgeworth, F. Y. 1881. Mathematical psychics: An essay on the
application of mathematics to the moral sciences. London: Kegan Paul. Edwards, J. 2005. Is
consciousness only a property of individual cells? Journal of Consciousness
Studies 12: 429–457. Available online http://www.ucl.ac.uk/jonathan-edwards/publications/conscpropcells
(accessed June 9, 2014). Fechner, G. 1873. Einige ideen zur schöpfungs- und
entwickelungsgeschichte der organismen. Leipzig: Breitkopf & Härtel. Freud, S. 1899. Die traumdeutung. Leipzig: Franz Deuticke. Freud, S. 1920. Beyond the pleasure principle. London: Hogarth. Friston, K. 2010. The free-energy
principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience 11:
127–138. Friston, K., J. Daunizeau, J.
Kilner, and S. J. Kiebel. 2010. Action and behavior: A free-energy formulation.
Biological Cybernetics 102: 227–260. Gossen, H. H. 1854. Entwickelung
der gesetze des menschlichen verkehrs, und der daraus fliessenden regeln für menschliche. Braunschweig: Vieweg. Huxley, A. 1932. Brave new world. London: Chatto & Windus. Jevons, W. S. 1871. Theory of political economy. London: Macmillan. Kluever, H. and P.
C. Bucy. 1938. An
analysis of certain effects of
bilateral temporal lobectomy in the rhesus monkey, with special reference to
“psychic blindness.” Journal of Psychology 5: 33–54. Koch, C. and I. Segev. 2000. The role of single neurons
in information processing. Nature
Neuroscience 3: 1171–1177. Available online http://www.anc.upmc.fr/teaching/UE_NB045/docs/KochSegev2000.pdf
(accessed June 9, 2014). Kosarev, V. 1997. Who will live on the Earth in XXI century? Neva
(in Russian) 1997(10): 135–149. Available online http://vlad-kos.narod.ru/NEVA1.html
(accessed June 9, 2014). Kringelbach, M. L. and K. C. Berridge. 2006. Towards a functional
anatomy of pleasure and happiness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13:
479–487. Lem, S. 1961. Solaris. Warsaw: Wydawnictwo MON. Menger, C. 1871. Grundsätze der volkswirtschaftslehre. Wien: W. Braumüller. Metzinger, T. (ed.). 2000. The neural correlates of consciousness.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Mill, J. S. 1863. Utilitarianism. London: Parker, Son, and Bourn. Murik, S. E. 1996. The relation of emotions to polarization proñesses in sensory systems. International Journal of Neuroscience
88: 185–197. Murik, S. E. 2006. General neural mechanisms of motivations and
emotions (in Russian). Irkutsk: Irkutsk State University Press. Olds, J. and P. Milner. 1954. Positive reinforcement produced by
electrical stimulation of septal area and other regions of rat brain. Journal
of Comparative and Physiological Psychology 47: 419-427. Pearce, D. 2005. The hedonistic imperative. Available online http://www.hedweb.com/hedethic/hedonist.htm
(accessed June 9, 2014). Pearce, D. 2014. Utilitronium shockwaves? Unsorted Facebook postings.
Available online http://www.hedweb.com/social-media/pre2014.html
(accessed July 19, 2014). Pyatygin, S. S., V. A.
Vodeneev, and V. A. Opritov. 2006. Depolarization of plasma membrane as the
universal primary bioelectric response of plant cells to action of different
factors. Advances in Current Biology (in Russian) 126: 493–502. Russell, B. 1946. History of western philosophy. London: Allen
and Unwin. Schultz,
W., P. Dayan, and P. R. Montague. 1997. A neural substrate of
prediction and reward. Science 275(5306): 1593–1599. Sem-Jacobsen, Ñ. W. and O. B.
Styri. 1972. Depth-electrographic stereotaxic psychosurgery. In Psychosurgery,
ed. E. Hitchcock, L. Laitinen, and K. Vaernet, 76–82. Springfield: C.C.
Thomas. Simonov, P. V. 1966.What is emotion (in Russian). Moscow: Science
(in Russian: Nauka). Simonov, P. V. 1986. The emotional brain: Physiology, neuroanatomy,
psychology and emotion. New York: Springer. Sevush, S. 2006.
Single-neuron theory of consciousness. Journal of Theoretical Biology
238: 704–725. Available online http://stevensevush.com
(accessed June 9, 2014). Shvyrkov, V. B. 1995. Introduction
to objective psychology: Neuronal basis of mind (in Russian). Moscow:
Institute of Psychology of the Russian Academy of Sciences Press. Smith, K. S. and K. C. Berridge. 2007. Opioid limbic circuit for reward:
interaction between hedonic hotspots of nucleus accumbens and ventral pallidum.
Journal of Neuroscience 27: 1594–1605. Walras, M.-É.-L. 1874. Éléments d'économie politique
pure, ou théorie de la richesse sociale. Lausanne: Corbaz. Wu, M. F., Zh. P. Pang,
M. Zhuo, and Z. C. Xu, 2005. Prolonged
membrane potential depolarization in cingulate pyramidal cell after digit
amputation in adult rats. Molecular Pain 1: 23-27. |