The Concept of the Posthuman: Chain of
Being Daryl J.
Wennemann Fontbonne
University dwennemann@fontbonne.edu Journal of Evolution and Technology - Vol. 26 Issue 2 – July 2016 - pgs 16-30
To the wise man, nothing is foreign or impassable. Antisthenes1 There
are many divers ways and modes of surpassing:
see thou thereto! But only a buffoon
thinks: Òman can also be overleapt.Ó Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche2 Abstract A central task in
understanding the theme of the posthuman involves relating it to the concept of
the human. For some, there is continuity between the concepts of the human and
the posthuman. This approach can be understood in the tradition of the great
chain of being. Another
approach posits a conceptual, and perhaps ontological, saltus (μετάβασις
εἰς ἄλλο γένος).
Here, the concept of the posthuman is taken to represent a radical departure
from the realm of the human. After considering LovejoyÕs scheme of the great
chain of being, AristotleÕs view of a conceptual saltus
(μετάβασις εἰς ἄλλο
γένος), and their historical significance, I will
suggest how we might distinguish various concepts of the posthuman from the
human by applying Rudolf CarnapÕs approach to defining multiple concepts of
space. We can thus create a linguistic convention that will assist in
constructing useful conceptions of the human and posthuman – these can
clarify the prospects of a posthuman future. Introduction The theme of the posthuman is gaining
significant traction in the disciplines of anthropology, cultural studies,
literary theory, and philosophy. But how are we to conceive of the posthuman? Kevin LaGrandeur has remarked that the meaning of the
terms ÒposthumanÓ and ÒtranshumanÓ are ambiguous. ÒAs post- and transhumanism have become
ever-hotter topics over the past decade or so, their boundaries have become
muddled by misappropriations and misunderstandings of what defines them, and
especially what distinguishes them from each otherÓ (2015, 49). According
to one conception, the meaning of the term ÒpostÓ in this context implies some
continuity between the human and the posthuman, since it is only in relation to
the human that we refer to the posthuman. Another approach posits a radical
hiatus between the human and the posthuman, supposedly indicated by the prefix
Òpost.Ó I will explore these two approaches to the posthuman by applying the
traditional great chain of being conception of reality and the notion of a
saltus, or conceptual leap, that can be traced to AristotleÕs concern with μετάβασις
in order to disambiguate differing meanings of the term ÒpostÓ and so gain some
purchase on the theme of posthumanity. As we shall see, KantÕs reflections on
the self-conflicting interests of reason, expressed in the laws of homogeneity
and specification, may be applied to contemporary theorizing about the
posthuman: This twofold
interest manifests itself also among students of nature in the diversity of
their ways of thinking. Those who are more especially speculative are, we may
almost say, hostile to heterogeneity, and are always on the watch for the unity
of the genus; those, on the other hand, who are more especially empirical, are
constantly endeavoring to differentiate nature in such manifold fashion as
almost to extinguish the hope of ever being able to determine its appearances
in accord with universal principles. (Kant 1965, 540, A 655/B683)3 The interest in homogeneity underlies the great chain of
being approach to the concept of the posthuman and the interest in
specification motivates the conceptual saltus approach. The great chain of being The idea of a great chain of being has
been a dominant motif in the Western philosophical tradition. Arthur O. Lovejoy
traced the idea to the philosophy of Plato. The divided line analogy in PlatoÕs
philosophy appears in The Republic (509d–510a). It posits a continuity between various
grades of being. The proportion represented on the divided line provides for
grades of intelligibility running throughout and across the different grades of
being, from images and physical entities of the visible world of becoming
(represented by sections A–B of the table below), to mathematical
ideas and the forms of various kinds of beings and the virtues. The latter
comprise the intelligible world of being (represented by sections C–D of the table): Such a conception of reality does not
allow gaps from one kind or grade of being to another. The philosophical roots
of this conception reach back to the ancient Greek philosopher Parmenides. For
Parmenides, non-being is not something real and cannot be thought without
contradiction, since we can think of non-being only in terms of being. This
insight informed the chain of being conception of reality that Plato developed,
such that there must be a continuity in the transition from one kind of being
to another. Within this philosophical tradition, therefore, nature abhors an
ontological vacuum. According to the Encyclopaedia Britannica (2015), The term [chain of being] denotes three general features of
the universe: plenitude, continuity, and gradation. The principle of plenitude
states that the universe is Òfull,Ó exhibiting the maximal diversity of kinds
of existences; everything possible (i.e., not self-contradictory) is actual. The
principle of continuity asserts that the universe is composed of an infinite
series of forms, each of which shares with its neighbour at least one
attribute. According to the principle of linear gradation, this series ranges
in hierarchical order from the barest type of existence to the ens perfectissimum, or God. This view of reality can be seen in the
conviction of modern physicists that there must exist elements on the periodic
table where there appears to be a gap. It can also be glimpsed in the scala
naturae conception of Darwinian evolution whereby there must not be missing
links in the development of species. Lovejoy opined in 1936 that the concept of
the great chain of being had informed not only philosophy but science and
poetry. And yet, he found it to be unfamiliar to many, including some
well-educated persons: The
title of this book [The Great Chain of Being], I find, seems to some not
unlearned persons odd, and its subject unfamiliar. Yet the phrase which I have
taken for the title was long one of the most famous in the vocabulary of
Occidental philosophy, science, and reflective poetry; and the conception which
in modern times came to be expressed by this or similar phrases has been one of
the half-dozen most potent and persistent presuppositions in Western thought.
It was, in fact, until not much more than a century ago, probably the most
widely familiar conception of the general scheme of things, of the
constitutive pattern of the universe; and as such it necessarily predetermined
current ideas on many other matters. (Lovejoy 1965, viii; italics in the
original) Now, I believe that the traditional
idea of the great chain of being can contribute to our understanding of some
conceptions of the posthuman. From this perspective, the posthuman is
understood in relation to the human. Even if there is a radical departure from
the human, according to this scheme, there is still continuity in development
from one kind to the other. There are several examples of this kind of
development that can be seen in the literature to date on the concept of the posthuman. First, we have the attempt to emulate
human cognition through the scanning of the human brain and the development of
neural models (Sandberg and Bostrom 2008). Here there is a continuity in the
functioning of the brain and a computer simulation. Human cognition is given a
new non-biological platform for its functioning. The increase in the speed of
computerized cognition would make for a posthuman being but the model of
cognition would remain human. Another approach to the posthuman, one considered
by Francis Fukuyama in Our Posthuman Future (2000), involves the genetic
modification of human beings. Again, while there may be a break between the
human and the posthuman, there is also discernible continuity inasmuch as we
can identify the new posthuman being over against the human. There is yet another approach to the
posthuman that seems to combine a break and a continuity with the human. Chris
Hables GrayÕs work Cyborg Citizen explores the ways in which our own
cyborgization can allow us to shape our subjectivity. It is interesting, in
this context, that Gray distinguishes between cyborgs and Òpure humansÓ (Gray 2002, 131). He notes that cyborgs are proliferating and redefining
many of the most basic political concepts of human existence (2002, 19) and
that new cyborg citizens must find ways to protect their rights (2002, 29). He
also notes that our only choice is to proliferate human and posthuman
possibilities. In the end, he believes we will be able to live longer and better
than ever before, pushing Òthe species into new, enlightening adventures in
inner and outer spacesÓ (2002, 201). This conception of the posthuman seems to
rely upon a continuity in the movement from the human to the posthuman. It is
as if every possible niche in the spectrum of our self-cyborgization must be
filled. The human imagination spins possible worlds, and contemporary
technoscience fills the void between the possible and the actual: At
the core of this web are the cyborg technosciences, which are extremely
evocative technologies – evocative not just in terms of what they provoke
from us as individuals, but especially in what possible futures they might
evoke for our culture as a whole. Dreaming of possible constructions of the
impossible leads to real transformations, new types of life, changes in the
very way we think of space, time, erotics, art, artificiality, perfection, and
life, ourselves. Technoscience is constantly deconstructing the idea of the
impossible. (2002, 194) A central issue in the posthuman age,
in my view, is whether our imaginations might have a disciplining function
rather than leaving us in what S¿ren
Kierkegaard called Òthe despair of possibility.Ó In this regard, Arjun
Appadurai has noted as follows: In
fact, it may be more useful to see design as trying to regulate fashion by
slowing down the infinite play of combinatorial possibilities, the dizzying
vista of new arrangements of bodies, materials, forms, and functions that
advertising daily puts before us. And
this might lead us closer to the logic of connecting design and context than
the conventional idea that design, being the loyal servant of fashion, simply
adds technique to the lust for change that defines fashion. Design certainly
involves the imagination, but it is defined by the imagination as a source of
discipline and not imagination merely as a source of new possibilities for
combination and cohabitation among objects. (Appadurai 2013, 263) The great chain of being approach to
the posthuman may be seen as registering a revolt against the eclipse of the
human by the posthuman. From this perspective, posthuman beings represent a
loss of humanity even when, and perhaps because, there is a leap in the power
available to enhanced human beings. An increase in the quantity of power at our
disposal results in a decrease in the qualitative character of human existence.
Arthur Kroker expresses this concern in his Exits to the Posthuman Future: If
it is the case that the sheer force of technological innovation quickly pushes
traditional conceptions of humanism aside to make way for all the emerging
signs of the posthuman – drift culture, recombinant technology,
figural aesthetics, distributive consciousness –
then it is true that something indispensably human, whether articulated by
conscious political protest, mobilized by social unrest, or motivated by the
persistence of human memory itself, remains as the phantasmagorical essence of
the future of technological posthumanism. (Kroker 2014, 4) Kroker sees the posthuman future as
undermining all of the previous ÒhumanÓ markers including a unitary
species-logic, private subjectivity, and hierarchical knowledge. This latter
marker posits human beings as Òthe universal value-standard of all eventsÓ
(Kroker 2014, 5). If there is a leap from the human to the posthuman, the great
chain of being mentality senses a continuity within the gap even if it is only
the presence of an absence. And so, Kroker argues that the technological
society is motivated by the return of the repressed. The shadow of the human
haunts the posthuman as a loss. The
leap into the posthuman future In contradistinction to the motif of
the great chain of being, we may posit that of a leap into the posthuman
future. Perhaps it is because Western thought has typically conceived of
reality as a great chain of being that the notion of a leap from one kind to
another has historically been seen as ontologically anomalous and logically
illicit. Aristotle identified a flaw in our reasoning that involves making a
discontinuous conceptual leap from one kind or genus to another, a metabasis
eis allo genos (μετάβασις
εἰς ἄλλο γένος).
Such a saltus renders a demonstration invalid and unscientific by introducing
ambiguity into the meaning of the terms we use in an argument. John K. OÕConnor notes that such a flawed
demonstration is not just a matter of an invalid syllogism: Ò[A]lthough it is
possible to shift from one genus into another in the course of a syllogism
without affecting the formal evaluation of the syllogism, such a transition
generally prevents the syllogism from rising to the level of scienceÓ (OÕConnor
2008, 739). The reason for this lies in AristotleÕs conception of a science.
Since every science is defined by a genus of being with which it is concerned,
to leap from one genus to another is to cross a scientific boundary.
Admittedly, it is possible for a science to borrow from a higher genus, as when
optics borrows from geometry (OÕConnor 2008, 742, n. 19). But, in general,
Aristotle was concerned with maintaining scientific boundaries. This required
that a scientific demonstration remain exclusively within a single genus of
being. Hence, for Aristotle, each science was defined by, and tied to, the
genus of its subject matter. For a demonstration to fail to remain within a
single genus is for it to commit a metabasis
eis allo genos. In moving from one genus to another the chain of essential
relations is broken, resulting in a failure to demonstrate the conclusion
(OÕConnor 2008, 741). If we glance forward to the philosophy
of Immanuel Kant, we can see that he was keenly aware of the character of the
transitions (†bergang) in his thought. The Groundwork is divided
according to three transitions. The first is a transition from common rational
to philosophical moral cognition (4:393)4. The second is the
transition from popular moral philosophy to metaphysics of morals (4:406). The
third is a transition from metaphysics of morals to the critique of pure
practical reason (4:446). KantÕs Metaphysical Foundations of Physical
Science may also be seen as providing a transition from the general
metaphysics of nature to a special metaphysics of nature (Plaass 1994, x, xi).
And at the time of his death, Kant left unfinished a work titled Transition
from the Metaphysical Foundations to Physics (Plaass 1994, 48–49).5 A significant part of KantÕs critique
of traditional metaphysics involved pointing to illegitimate leaps in thought.
And so, metabasis had a significant role in his epistemology. Kant
recognized that human reason tends to pose questions that we cannot answer. It
also has a tendency to go beyond its own limits in seeking the ultimate basis
of our experience. For example, in the thesis of the fourth antinomy concerning
the cosmological proof for the existence of God, Kant noted that some thinkers
have taken the liberty of making a conceptual leap (metabasis eis allo genos), moving from the existence of
contingent empirical objects to the existence of a necessary being, which he
judged to be an illegitimate saltus (Kant 1965, 419, A 461/B 489). Again, in
the Religion, Kant argued that it is
a mistake to transform a schematism of analogy into one of object-determination:
ÒBut between the relationship of a schema to its concept and the relationship
of this very schema of the concept to the thing itself there is no analogy, but
a formidable leap (μετάβασις
εἰς ἄλλο γένος)
which leads straight into anthropomorphismÓ (Kant 1996, 107, 6: 65, note).
Finally, Kant argued that there is a law of homogeneity that is posited by
reason as a heuristic device that makes our experience possible. Accordingly,
Òall differences of species border upon one another, admitting of no transition
from one to another per saltum, but
only through all the smaller degrees of difference that mediate between themÓ (Kant
1965, 543, A 659/B 687; italics in the original). OÕConnor argues that the conception of
an Òincidental, argument-level metabasisÓ can easily be extended to
Òsystemic foundational metabasisÓ (2008, 742, italics in the original). He
finds that this was the course of development that informed the philosophy of
Franz Brentano and then Edmund Husserl. BrentanoÕs concern was to differentiate
the scientific boundaries of psychology and physiology. This may have been a
basis for HusserlÕs later distinction between transcendental phenomenology and
descriptive psychology (cf., OÕConnor 2008, 743). Brentano was also concerned
to avoid equivocation and he considered metabasis to be a source of
equivocation (2008, 743). Can a leap across a chasm from one kind
to another be legitimate? According to Louis P. Pojman, Kierkegaard conceived
of freedom as a leap beyond the realm of natural determination: In the last
analysis freedom as voluntary choice happens in the eternal ÒNowÓ which breaks
into the normal course of determined action. It is a metabasis eis allo genos (something of an altogether other dimension
from ordinary events), a mystery which signals divine grace and omnipotence.
(Pojman 1990, 49)6 Here, in its most profound significance,
the metabasis eis allo genos
implicated in human freedom is not a mere conceptual inference but may bring
about a transition from one stage of life to another. It may be that the transition from the
human to the posthuman is a leap of faith of a sort. For those who have faith
in the progressive character of technology, the movement to the posthuman holds
forth the possibility of an advance and improvement over against the human.
Kevin LaGrandeur notes, in this regard, that a posthuman condition is one to
which transhumanists aspire. Various technological developments may be seen in
this context as bringing about a qualitative leap from one kind to another. The
posthuman can thus be understood in terms of a metabasis eis allo genos: Basically,
transhumanists believe in improving the human species by using any and every
form of emerging technology. Technology is meant in the broad sense here: it
includes everything from pharmaceuticals to digital technology, genetic
modification to nanotechnology. The posthuman is the state that transhumans
aspire to: a state in which our species is both morally and physically improved,
and maybe immortal – a species improved to the point where we perhaps
become a different (and thus ÒposthumanÓ) species altogether. (LaGrandeur 2015,
49) The approach to the posthuman that is
conceived in terms of an ontological leap from the human to the posthuman seems
to have as its strategy to recognize the ontological gap between diverse kinds
of things without falling into the trap of anthropomorphism. The interest of
reason expressed in the law of specification motivates this approach. It is remarkable
that the kind of insight involved in recognizing the posthuman as requiring a
cognitive leap to a new kind of being that is discontinuous with the human
would seem to require a peculiarly human form of cognition. According to Jeremy
Campbell, Computers are
good at swift, accurate computation and at storing great masses of information.
The brain, on the other hand, is not as efficient a number cruncher and its
memory is often highly fallible; a basic inexactness is built into its design.
The brainÕs strong point is its flexibility. It is unsurpassed at making shrewd
guesses and at grasping the total meaning of information presented to it.
(Campbell 1982, 190) Such cognitive leaps may be a
distinguishing mark of the human over against the posthuman, unless and until
posthuman beings become capable of it. But then, from the perspective of a
transcendental posthumanism, the difficulty arises as to whether a radically
alien posthuman being could be cognized. Could we recognize a posthuman person
as a person if the character of its existence lay outside and beyond any
categories of personhood available to us? Does such an approach exhibit a
fascination with the strange, the alien, that which is foreign and unknown?
There is a human need for mystery that this approach might satisfy. But, then
again, the strangeness of this approach might just indicate that we are on the
right track in our attempt to comprehend the posthuman. Jeremy Campbell notes
that in one of Dorothy L. SayersÕ novels, the character Lord Peter Whimsey
finds that the reason for a certain satisfaction in some new evidence in a
murder he is investigating is that it adds
the final touch of utter and impenetrable obscurity to the problem which the
inspector and I have undertaken to solve. It reduces it to the complete
quintessence of incomprehensible nonsense. Therefore, by the second law of
thermo-dynamics, which lays down that we are hourly and momently progressing to
a state of more and more randomness, we receive positive assurance that we are
moving happily and securely in the right direction. (Sayers 1932, 236; cited in
Campbell 1982, 52) If, in his treatment of the human, Albert
Camus found it necessary to focus on the strangeness of existence (Camus 1993),
perhaps it is to be expected that the development of a posthuman existence
would be strange to us. Camus held that human
existence is absurd since we live in a world that does not meet our needs.
Rebellion is a response to this condition that expresses Òhope for a new
creation. Man is the only creature who refuses to be what he is. The problem is
to know whether this refusal can only lead to the destruction of himself and of
othersÉÓ (Camus 1993, 11). Part of the challenge of the movement toward the
posthuman, from the perspective of CamusÕ philosophy, is whether this new creation
will overcome the absurdity of existence or whether the refusal to be ourselves
will lead to our self-destruction. Or, will posthuman beings not feel the need
to rebel? In Posthuman
Life, David Roden provides an account of the posthuman that seems to break
the bounds of sense in that it attempts to conceive of an utterly alien being
that lies beyond our ability to cognize. Roden posits a sort of ontological
rupture that he designates as a ÒdisconnectionÓ from the human in order to give
the prefix ÒpostÓ its most fundamental meaning (Roden 2015, 8 et passim).
According to his conception, a breach in continuity between the human and the
posthuman is necessary to adequately grasp the posthuman. But it is not a
difference between kinds of being, in his view, but a difference between
individuals. Still, a philosophical consideration of the posthuman would thus
seem to require a metabasis. Interestingly, the Greek term ÒgenosÓ (γένος)
can have the meaning Òoffspring,
even a single descendant, a childÓ
(Liddell and Scott 1889). And so, RodenÕs account may be said to involve
a metabasis eis allo genos,
if the image of the posthuman as the offspring of the human does not imply too
close a tie between them. Since a leap must be from somewhere to a place beyond
a gap, we can see RodenÕs leap to the posthuman as proceeding from the human.
Roden acknowledges this in a recent interview: ÒThis being said, I acknowledge
that my characterization of the posthuman is human-relative. The disconnection
thesis describes the posthuman in terms of the capacity of posthumans cut free
from the Wide HumanÓ (Bakker 2015, 167). Carnapian construction In a previous work, Posthuman Personhood (2013), I introduced a linguistic convention
in order to disambiguate different meanings of the term Òhuman.Ó Following the
lead of Rudolf Carnap, I used superscripts to designate biological humanity
with the term ÒhumanBÓ and moral humanity with the term ÒhumanMÓ.
The term ÒhumanMÓ refers to the class of persons (in the moral
sense), as opposed to genetically human beings or humansB. Note
again LaGrandeurÕs distinction between these two dimensions of the human, ÒThe
posthuman is the state that transhumans aspire to: a state in which our species
is both morally and physically improvedÉÓ (LaGrandeur 2015, 49). We should
consider the possibility that our species could be physically ÒimprovedÓ but
not morally improved. It may also be possible that the species could be morally
improved without being physically improved. In a more recent work, ÒPosthumanisms: A
Carnapian ExperimentÓ (2015), I sought to disambiguate the term ÒpostÓ so as to
distinguish different senses of the term Òposthuman.Ó We can thus conceptualize
a hypo posthumanism and a hyper posthumanism, designated by the terms ÒpostohumanBÓ and ÒpostRhumanBÓ
respectively.9 Carnap
held that our received folk language is so shot through with ambiguity that it
must be altered to render it amenable for philosophical work. He promoted a
principle of tolerance that allows for each of us to create our own language in
order to clearly express our thought. What he considered imperative was that each
person specify just what language s/he uses. Consider CarnapÕs treatment of the
concept of space. In CarnapÕs
Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism,
Alan W. Richardson substitutes the English term ÒspaceÓ for the German term Òraum.Ó Richardson explains that Carnap
recognized a distinction between formal space, designated by the letter S, intuitive space, designated by the term
S′, and physical space, designated by S′′. He further
recognized a distinction between topological, projective, and metrical space,
designated by the letters t, p, and m, respectively. Each of these could have a
dimensional variant designated by numbers or the letter n: ÒThus, for example,
S′4t designates four-dimensional topological intuitive space, and Snp
designates projective formal space of arbitrarily many dimensionsÓ (Richardson
1998, 141). Part of CarnapÕs argument was that philosophical disputes over the
concept of space could generally be resolved by using terms that distinguish
these different concepts. It is plain that to simply speak of space would be
impossibly ambiguous. Likewise, disputes over the character of
the posthuman may be traced to the diverse meanings given to the term
Òposthuman.Ó The possibility of adequately conceptualizing the posthuman is
hopeless if the term is used with divergent meanings so that readers seeing it
have widely divergent ideas of what is being discussed. John Locke made a
similar observation in An Essay
Concerning Human Understanding (1689): ÒThe chief End of Language in
Communication being to be understood, Words serve not well for that end,
neither in civil, nor in philosophical Discourse, when any Word does not excite
in the Hearer, the same Idea which it stands for in the Mind of the SpeakerÓ
(Locke 1975, bk III, ch. 4. IX, º 4, 476–77). My hope is that my terminological
conventions might clarify some of the ambiguity surrounding the use of the term
Òposthuman,Ó whether it is conceived according to the model of the great chain
of being or a conceptual saltus. The central Carnapian insight here is that
disambiguating the term ÒposthumanÓ can clarify philosophical disputes
surrounding the issue of the posthuman. It also serves to illustrate that the
area of the posthuman is not a unified field of study. There are, rather,
diverse approaches. Some scholars seek a continuity of the human and posthuman
in order to maintain a grasp on the posthuman reality. Others see a rupture
with the human, posing both a thrilling possibility and a threat. For some,
including Francis Fukuyama and Arthur Kroker, our posthumanB future holds the possibility of a loss
of personal existence through the genetic manipulation of humanB beings. This scenario depicts a
hypo-posthumanB condition.
It represents a decline in humanB existence that could result from
the increase in speed and power associated with various technological
developments, perhaps because of unintended effects of genetic manipulation. We
could designate this sense of a posthumanB condition by the term ÒpostohumanBÓ
or ÒpohB.Ó And since there is a decline in the
possibility of a moral dimension associated with this condition, there is also
a damaging of the humanM condition.
The postohumanB may
thus be correlated with a postohumanM- (pohM-) order. Such a being could be
conceived as postohumanB/postohumanM-
(pohB/M-). The
technological enhancements that are often associated with transhumanism may
also be conceived as leading to a hyper-posthumanB condition. On this approach, humanB beings might be altered pharmacologically
or through cyber technologies (implants, prostheses) or genetic engineering to
produce a possibly more rational, empathetic, and thus more morally advanced
humanM being. It is also
possible that computers or robots might be produced that are not humanB but morally superior in some ways to
humanB beings (Wallach
2008). This hyper-posthumanB condition
can be designated by the term ÒpostRhumanBÓ or ÒpRhBÓ.
Because such a hyper-posthumanB condition
also results in an improvement in the ability of posthumanB beings to carry out a personal
existence, it would be designated ÒpostRhumanM+ Ó or ÒpRhM+ Ó. While the
complex classification pRhB/M+ applies in this
case, since a morally hyper-posthuman being (pRhM+) can
only be associated with a hyper-posthumanB being (pRhB),
we can refer to a morally hyper-posthuman being (pRhM+)
and it is then implied that it is hyper-posthumanB (pRhB).
The term ÒposthumanÓ has such a positive connotation for Rosi Braidotti: [T]o be posthuman does not mean to be indifferent to the
humans, or to be de-humanized. On the contrary, it rather implies a new way of
combining ethical values with the well-being of an enlarged sense of community,
which includes oneÕs territorial or environmental inter-connections. (Braidotti
2013, 190) However, a
hyper-posthumanB condition
might also produce a posthumanB being
that possesses increased intelligence, etc., while lacking a moral sense or
possessing a distorted moral sense (a moral monster like Star TrekÕs Khan Noonien Singh). This is the concern that Wendell
Wallach and others, such as Nick Bostrom, have explored with respect to the
possibility of creating moral machines. Superintelligence does not necessarily
correlate with a superior personal existence (Bostrom 2014). Depending on the
circumstances, a hyper-posthumanB condition
might have a positive or negative moral valuation. Accordingly, I propose to
designate a hyper-posthumanB condition that could Òlead to a very
rapid extinction of all humans, or something even more hellishÓ (Roden 2012) as
ÒpostRhumanM- Ó or ÒpRhM- Ó. And so, we can see that a postRhumanB condition might be correlated with a
moral advance or decline, whereas a postohumanB condition must necessarily represent a
moral decline. Thus, any
discussion of a hypo-posthuman moral being (postohumanM-)
must be qualified as to whether it is biologically hypo-posthuman (pohB)
or biologically hyper-posthumanB (postRhB). A
biologically hyper-posthuman moral being may thus be designated pRhB/M+
or pRhB/p0M-. (It is embarrassing
that scientists should employ a complex language to describe the physical world
whereas philosophers are content to speak of Òthe posthuman.Ó) There is,
finally, a posthumanB condition that would represent a state in
which posthumanB persons are equal to humanB persons in
their ability to exercise a personal existence (such a posthumanB
person might, perhaps, be a robot that cannot be distinguished from a humanB
being (posthumanB) or a humanB being who has been altered
pharmacologically to improve mood or memory but remains within the range of
humanB performance (postRhumanB)).10 I designate this possibility by the term
ÒposthumanB/M=Ó or ÒpostRhumanM=Ó. It
would be posthumanM in the sense that it is a post-anthroBpocene
person. A morally posthuman person (posthumanM=/+) is thus a
subclass of moral humanity (humanM), along with humanB
beings. It is not a post-person in the sense of having surpassed personhood. By
way of analogy, if the term ÒaviationÓ were taken to include all forms of
flight, we could distinguish between Òavian aviationÓ and Òpost-avian aviationÓ
in the case of artificially powered flight. And so, a posthumanB
humanM would be a person that exercises a personal existence in a
way different from the way in which a humanB humanM being
does. The mode of cognition of a computer need not be the same as that of a
humanB being, and nor does an airplane have to flap its wings to
fly. Thus, ÒThe Ôimitation gameÕ of the Turing Test has misdirected the
ambitions of AI, just as a concern with feathers and flapping misdirected early
efforts at flightÓ (Ford 2016). To
illustrate these distinctions further, I would first like to posit a partial
posthuman condition (designated by the term ÒPPosthumanB) which can
be seen to represent a state between that of the humanB and the
posthumanB. Max More has remarked, in this regard, that we have
taken the first steps in producing posthuman beings: Clearly we have already taken our first steps along the road
to posthumanity É We have achieved two of the three alchemistsÕ dreams: We have
transmuted the elements and learned to fly. Immortality is next É Humanity
must not stagnate: to halt our burgeoning move forward, upward, outward, would
be a betrayal of the dynamic inherent in life and consciousness. Let us
progress on into a posthuman stage that we can barely glimpse. (More 1994) If we
recognize a partial posthumanB condition, as a chain of being
mentality would tend to do, transhumanism may be taken to seek the equivalent of
a partial hyper-posthumanB being (PPostRhumanB)
that corresponds to a partial hyper-posthumanM condition with a
positive moral valence (PPostRhumanM+)
or ppRhB/M+. Such a positive connotation to the term
ÒPPostRhumanB/M+Ó (or sometimes ÒtranshumanÓ) is typical
of transhumanist theorizing. Partial posthumanB possibilities may be
illustrated as: PPosthumanB = PPosthumanM= PPostohumanB = PPostohumanM- PPostRhumanB = PPostRhumanM= PPostRhumanB = PPostRhumanM- or
PPostRhumanM+
(= Transhuman) (ppRhB/M+) We may also posit an end-state model of
the posthumanB that relates transhumanism to the posthumanB
in terms of its goal. Such a target state is what Amitai Etzioni designated, in
The Active Society, as a
Òfuture-systemÓ model. According to Etzioni, ÒThe active society is a
future-system for the analysis of post-modern historyÓ (1968, 572 n). Here the transhuman
(or the state of transition postulated by transhumanists) may be seen as
leading to either a hypo-posthumanB condition, a hyper-posthumanB
condition, or a posthumanB condition. A transhumanism that results
in a hypo-posthumanB condition or a posthumanB one, is a
failed transhumanism since transhumanists seek an improved humanB
condition both physically and morally. The Carnapian approach to concept
construction illustrates the variations that are possible in our conception of
the posthumanB: HumanB - PPosthumanB /PPostRhumanB = PosthumanM= / PostRhumanM= HumanB -
PPostohumanB
= PostohumanM- HumanB - PPostRhumanB = PostRhumanM- HumanB - PPostRhumanB = PostRhumanM+ Posthuman
prospects There
are multiple paths to the posthumanB, one of which holds forth the possibility of an
improvement of the humanB species, both biologically and
morally. This is what attracts us to the technologies implicated in the
transhumanist movement. The allure of emerging technologies is the allure of
the possibilities they symbolize. Kierkegaard famously analyzed the role of
possibility in humanB experience and its relation to despair; in
addition to the despair of possibility, he identified a despair of necessity.
Responding to KierkegaardÕs work, Jacques Ellul found both of these forms of
despair to be present in the elaboration of the technological system. As Ellul
remarked, quoting Kierkegaard from Sickness
unto Death, When technology
makes everything possible, then it becomes itself the absolute necessity.
Necessity which was once the mother of invention, has created an inventive
process which is the mother of a new necessity. ÒThe loss of possibility
signifies: either that everything has become necessary É or that everything has
become trivial.Ó In fact, with modern technology, both happen at once. (Ellul
1984, 95) Will our attempt to enhance the cognitive
capacity of humanB
beings lead only to the loss of our ability to make decisions that are ours,
either because the genetic basis of humanM identity has been undermined (as Francis
Fukuyama fears) or because we have given over our decisions to a
superintelligence that is beyond our control (as Nick Bostrom worries)?
Politically, the emerging technologies giving rise to the posthumanB would seem to call for the
kind of democratic planning that Karl Mannheim endorsed, an idea James Hughes
(2004) has updated for the twenty-first century in terms of a democratic
transhumanism. However, if the technologies that can enhance humanB
beings can also be used to mold them so as to manage public opinion, the
approach of democratic planning may be what Ellul called a Òpolitical illusionÓ
(1972). Hans JonasÕ treatment of ethics in a technological age provides what is
perhaps the most honest assessment of our existential condition as we face the
posthumanB age: [I]t must be
admitted now that this same uncertainty of all long-term projections becomes a
grievous weakness when they have to serve as prognoses by which to mold
behavior – that is in the practical-political application of whatever
principles were apprehended with the help of the heuristic casuistry. É Being
so much in the dark, why not trust our luck including that of posterity? But in
this way, all the gains of our hypothetical heuristics are kept from timely
application by the inconclusiveness of the prognostics, and the finest principles
must lie fallow until it is, perhaps, too late. (Jonas 1985, 30) Do we even have principles that lie
fallow? Our condition is all the worse if we do not have orienting principles
to guide us in our technological self-alteration from humanB to posthumanB.
And if the movement toward the posthumanB is self-defeating, in that
the attempt to physically improve humanB beings undermines the
possibility of genuine moral improvement, then it seems that our existential
condition (as vulnerable, temporal beings, having imperfect knowledge of the
implications of technological developments) is the only source of orientation
we can rely upon to be able to stand still for a moment, so as to avoid the
whirl of change of emergent technologies. Western philosophy is rooted in an
attempt to find a place to stand so we could move the world. As we set out to
explore the vast ocean of the posthumanB we seem to need what John
P. Doyle called a Òphilosophical Finisterre.Ó Doyle explains, ÒFinisterre is a
cape in northern Spain at the westernmost point of the Spanish mainland. It
marks an end of Europe; beyond Finisterre there is only the oceanÓ (2012, 215). Doyle used Finisterre (the end of the
earth) as an image of the farthest point of philosophical speculation he found
the European philosophers of the seventeenth century had reached. For us, a
philosophical Finisterre is a jump off point into the vast ocean of
possibility, a foothold for philosophy at the edge of the human, to use RodenÕs
phrase. How might we respond to JonasÕ attitude of resignation regarding
philosophical ethics in a technological age beyond a mere leap of faith? [H]ere is where
I come to a standstill, where we all come to a standstill. For the very same
movement which put us in possession of the powers that have now to be regulated
by norms – the movement of modern knowledge called science – has by
a necessary complementarity eroded the foundations from which norms could be
derived; it has destroyed the very idea of norm as such. É Now we shiver in the
nakedness of a nihilism in which near-omnipotence is paired with
near-emptiness, greatest capacity with knowing least for what ends to use it.
(Jonas 1985, 22–23) Notes 1. See Diogenes Laertius 1925, 12. I have
altered HicksÕs English translation, replacing the term ÒimpracticableÓ with
the term Òimpassable.Ó Compare David Roden (2015, 177–78): ÒThe moral of
this tale is that differences in phenomenology can be significant obstructions
to our understanding without being impassable barriers.Ó 2. I have altered the
translation slightly (see Nietzsche 1917, 221). 3. Compare Pierre Bourdieu 1977, 230–31, n.
110: The
principle of this antinomy [of otherness and identity] was indicated by Kant in
the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic: depending on the interests which
inspire it, ÒreasonÓ obeys either the Òprinciple of specificationÓ which leads
it to seek and accentuate differences, or the Òprinciple of aggregationÓ or
Òhomogeneity,Ó which leads it to observe similarities, and, through an illusion
which characterizes it, ÒreasonÓ situates the principle of these judgments not
in itself but in the nature of its object.
(Italics in original) 4.
I have supplied the volume and page numbers for the Royal Prussian Academy of
Sciences edition of KantÕs works. 5.
Compare Plaass 1994, 311: ÒThere [in the Opus
Postumum] it is also frequently said that the MF would have a natural tendency towards ÔtransitionÕ or
Ôprogression to physicsÕ (eg., Altpreu§ische Monatsschrift, XIX, 126; XXI,
143).Ó 6.
Compare Nason 2014, 6: ÒThe movement of resignation, for de Silentio, is an act
he and every other human agent can do. ÔI can
make the mighty trampoline leap whereby I cross over into infinity; my back is
like a tightrope dancerÕs, twisted in my childhood, and therefore it is easy
for me.ÕÓ 7.
Compare Roden 2015, 6: Some philosophers claim that there are
features of human moral life and human subjectivity that are not just local to
certain gregarious primates but are necessary conditions of agency and
subjectivity everywhere. This Òtranscendental approachÓ to philosophy does not
imply that posthumans are impossible but that – contrary to expectations
– they might not be all that different from us. Thus a theory of
posthumanity should consider both empirical and transcendental constraints on
posthuman possibility. 8. Again compare Roden: In
that case, the possibility of posthumans implies that the future of life and
mind might not only be stranger than we imagine, but stranger than we can
currently conceive É Does this mean that talk of ÒposthumansÓ is self-vitiating
nonsense? (2015, 6) 9. The following is
developed from Wennemann 2015. 10. I am indebted to
Rebecca FoushŽe for pointing out this possibility. References Appadurai, Arjun. 2013. The future as
cultural fact: Essays on the global condition. London and
Brooklyn, NY: Verso. Bakker, R. Scott. 2015. Interview with
David Roden. Figure / Ground, June 6.
http://figureground.org/interview-with-david-roden/
(accessed July 5, 2016). Bostrom, Nick. 2014. Superintelligence: Paths, dangers, strategies. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline
of a theory of practice. New York: Cambridge University Press. Braidotti,
Rosi. 2013. The posthuman. Cambridge, UK, and Malden, MA: Polity Press. Campbell, Jeremy. 1982. Grammatical man: Information,
entropy, language and life. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Camus, Albert. 1993. The
Stranger. Trans. Matthew Ward. New York: Knopf.
(Orig. pub. in French 1942.) Diogenes Laertius. 1925. Lives of eminent
philosophers in ten books. Vol. 2
(bks 6–10). Trans. R.D.
Hicks. Loeb Classical Library ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Life of Antisthenes available online at http://www.loebclassics.com/view/diogenes_laertius-lives_eminent_philosophers_book_vi_chapter_1_antisthenes/1925/pb_LCL185.3.xml?rskey=3aQs90&result=79 (accessed July 5,
2016).) (Orig. pub. 3rd century CE.) Doyle, John P. 2012.
Supertranscendental nothing. In On the borders
of being and knowing: Late Scholastic Theory of Supertranscendental Being,
ed. Victor M. Sala, 215–41. Leuven: Leuven University Press. (Orig. pub.
as: Supertranscendental nothing: A philosophical Finisterre. Medioevo 24 (1998): 1–30.) Editors of Encyclop¾dia
Britannica. 2015. Great chain of being. http://www.britannica.com/topic/Great-Chain-of-Being (accessed July 5, 2016). Ellul, Jacques. 1972. The political illusion. New York:
Vintage. Ellul, Jacques. 1984. The
latest developments in technology and the philosophy of the absurd. In Research in philosophy & technology,
vol. 7, ed. Paul T. Durbin, 77–97. Greenwich, CN: JAI Press. Etzioni, Amitai. 1968. The active society: A theory of societal and political processes. New York: Free
Press.
Ford, Kenneth. 2016. Cognitive systems
seminar series: On computational wings? Institute for People and Technology
(Georgia Tech).
http://ipat.gatech.edu/hg/item/477961 (accessed July 5, 2016).
Fukuyama, Francis. 2000. Our
posthuman future: Consequences of the biotechnology revolution. New York:
Farrar, Strauss and Giroux. Gray,
Chris Hables. 2002. Cyborg citizen:
Politics in the posthuman age. New York: Routledge. Hughes, James. 2004.
Citizen cyborg: Why democratic societies must respond
to the redesigned human of the future. Cambridge, MA: Basic Books.
Jonas, Hans. 1985. The imperative of responsibility: In search of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 1965. Critique of pure reason. Trans. Norman
Kemp Smith. New York: St. MartinÕs Press. (2nd ed. orig. pub. 1781/1787.) Kant, Immanuel. 1996. Religion within the boundaries of mere
reason, trans. George Di Giovanni. In The
Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, Religion and Rational Theology, trans. and ed. Allen W. Wood and
George Di Giovanni. New York, Cambridge University Press. (Orig. pub. 1793.) Kroker, Arthur. 2014. Exits to the posthuman future.
Cambridge, UK, and Malden, MA: Polity Press. LaGrandeur, Kevin. 2015.
Book review: Robert Ranisch and Stefan Lorenz Sorgner, ed., Post- and Transhumanism: An Introduction.
Journal of Evolution and Technology
25(1) (June 2015): 49–52. Available online at http://jetpress.org/v25.1/lagrandeur.htm (accessed July 1, 2016). Liddell, Henry George,
and Robert Scott. 1889. An Intermediate Greek-English Lexicon. Available online at http://perseus.uchicago.edu/cgi-bin/philologic/navigate.pl?MiddleLiddell.2 (accessed July 6, 2016). Locke, John. 1975. An essay concerning human understanding.
Ed. Peter H. Nidditch. New York: Oxford University Press. (Orig. pub. 1689.) Lovejoy, Arthur O. 1965. The
great chain of being: A study of the
history of an idea. New York: Harper & Row. (Orig. pub. 1936.) More, Max. 1994. On becoming posthuman. Available online at http://eserver.org/courses/spring98/76101R/readings/becoming.html (accessed July 6, 2016). Nason, Shannon M. 2014. Movement/motion.
In KierkegaardÕs concepts Tome IV:
Individual to novel, ed. Steven Emmanuel, William McDonald, and Jon Stewart,
205–212. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate. An online version
available at: http://myweb.lmu.edu/snason/Research_and_Writing_files/Movement%20KRSRR.pdf (accessed July 6, 2016). Nietzsche, Friedrich, 1917, Thus Spake Zarathustra. Trans. Thomas Common. New York: Modern
Library. Available online at https://archive.org/details/thusspokezarathu00nietuoft (accessed July 6,
2016). OÕConnor, John K. 2008.
Precedents in Aristotle and Brentano for HusserlÕs concern with metabasis. Review of Metaphysics 61 (4) (June): 737–57. Plaass, Peter. 1994. KantÕs theory of natural science.
Trans., with introd. and commentary, Alfred E. and Maria G. Miller. Dordrecht:
Kluwer. Pojman, Louis P. 1990. Kierkegaard on faith and freedom. Philosophy of Religion 27: 41–61. Available online at http://www.sorenkierkegaard.nl/artikelen/Engels/134.%20Kierkegaard%20on%20faith%20and%20freedom.pdf (accessed July 5, 2016).
Richardson, Alan W.
1998. CarnapÕs construction of the world:
The Aufbau and the emergence of logical empiricism. Cambridge and New York:
Cambridge University Press. Roden, David. 2012. Humanism, transhumanism
and posthumanism. Website for enemyindustry: philosophy at the edge of the
human. (Posted June 12.)
http://enemyindustry.net/blog/?p=3348 (accessed July 6, 2016).
Roden, David. 2015. Posthuman Life: Philosophy
at the edge of the human. New York, Routledge.
Sandberg, A., and N. Bostrom, N. 2008. Whole brain emulation: A roadmap. Technical Report #2008‐3, Oxford: Future of
Humanity Institute (Oxford University). http://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/brain-emulation-roadmap-report.pdf (accessed July 6,
2016). Sayers, Dorothy L. 1932. Have
his carcase. New York: Avon Books. Wennemann, Daryl J. 2013. Posthuman personhood. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Wennemann,
Daryl. 2015. Posthumanisms: A Carnapian experiment. Ethical Technology blog. Institute
for Ethics and Emerging Technologies. (Posted March 19.) http://ieet.org/index.php/IEET/more/wennemann20150319 (accessed July 5,
2016). |