The Transhumanist
Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce1 Aaron B. Wilson
Journal of Evolution and Technology - Vol. 27 Issue 2 – December 2017 - pgs 12-29 Abstract We explain
how the work of Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914)
–
the
founder of semiotics and of the pragmatist tradition in philosophy –
contributes
an epistemological, metaphysical, and ethical foundation to some key transhumanist ideas, including the following claims: technological
cognitive enhancement is not only possible but a present reality; pursuing more
sweeping cognitive enhancements is epistemically
rational; and current
humans should try to evolve themselves into posthumans.
On Peirce’s view, the fundamental aim of inquiry is truth, understood in terms
of a stage of ideal cognition (what
he calls the “final opinion”). As current human cognitive abilities are
insufficient to achieve this stage, Peirce’s views on cognition support a
variety of ways in which they might be enhanced. Finally, we argue that what
Peirce describes as our ethical summum bonum seems remarkably similar to what Bostrom (2005) argues to be the core transhumanist
value: “the exploration of the posthuman realm.” Introduction In “A
History of Transhumanist Thought” (2005a), Nick Bostrom traces ideas about the promises of scientific
progress (e.g. indefinite life extension, cognitive enhancement, and expanded
control over nature) to a number of Renaissance and Enlightenment authors: Pico
della Mirandola, Francis
Bacon, Offray de La Mettrie,
and Nicolas de Condorcet.2 As
influential as scientific humanism was during the early modern period, in the
nineteenth century it strained against a tide of romantic thought and
“latter-day reactions against the rule of instrumental reason in the attempt to
rationally control nature” (Bostrom 2005a, 4) – which,
in the works of Thoreau and others, often invoke primitivist
or Luddite ideals. But nineteenth-century literature is far from bereft of transhumanist themes: some works by Mary Shelley, Jules
Verne, and H.G. Wells are notable exceptions. And though Nietzsche’s concept of
the Übermensch
is not an expression of a technologically
enhanced human, it is an expression of a person who, by rejecting all
traditional gods, aspires to his own sort of godhood. The prominence of transhumanist thought grew throughout the twentieth century
–
with
an explosion in the science fiction genre and with Julian Huxley (1951, 1957)
seemingly coining the term “transhumanism” –
before
becoming a distinct intellectual movement and focus of academic study by the beginning
of the twenty-first.3 One late
nineteenth- and early twentieth-century thinker whom Bostrom
does not mention, but whom he’d have had good reason to include, is the
scientist and philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914).
Peirce is widely known as a founder of both modern semiotics (the theory of
signs) and the pragmatist tradition in philosophy. But he should also be
recognized for articulating ideas that, even if not (yet) particularly
influential among transhumanist and posthumanist thinkers, can help guide transhumanist
thought today. There are some suggestions in the relevant literature that
Peirce may already have had some influence on transhumanism.
For instance, in the “Philosophy of Transhumanism,” Max
More mentions a “form of Piercean [sic] pragmatism”
as a popular epistemological view among transhumanists
(More 2013, 6). Peirce’s name does not come up often in the literature, but his
philosophy offers a normative and metaphysical framework for transhumanism. Not only do Peirce’s writings on ultimate
aims and values provide one possible basis for transhumanist
aims and values, his accounts of cognition, inquiry, and truth entail both the
possibility and the rationality of cognitive enhancement. It is
easy to miss this aspect of Peirce’s ideas, and Bostrom
cannot be blamed for overlooking him. It is unclear whether Peirce had directly
inspired any overtly transhumanist thinking at the
time when Bostrom was writing.4 But any attentive reader who is willing
to wade through the hundreds of pages of Peirce’s published and unpublished
writings will notice that some elements of his philosophical system
conspicuously align with transhumanism. One such
element is his account of truth. Peirce identifies truth as both the ultimate
aim of all inquiry and the ideal state of information. Assuming that human
inquirers would need to enhance their cognitive abilities in order to
indefinitely approach this ideal state, it becomes, on Peirce’s approach, epistemically or “logically” rational to do so.5
Further, Peirce upholds a form of the
extended mind thesis, or the thesis that some of our own cognitive
processes extend outside our skulls, which allows for much continuity between
cognition and technology (e.g., our cognitive abilities may be extended into,
and enhanced by, our smartphones). But perhaps the most fundamental connection
between Peirce’s thought and transhumanism is with
respect to values. This follows from his
conception of the summum bonum, or the
ultimate end of action, as well as a related conception of God. Peirce makes certain remarks suggesting that an approach to
Godhood is our summum bonum (which
comports with his view about truth). Bostrom (2005b)
expresses a similar idea when he identifies the
exploration of the posthuman realm as the ultimate aim or value for
the transhumanist. So, notwithstanding some
differences on details and terminology, there seems to be general agreement on
core values between Peirce and Bostrom-style transhumanism. We do not
necessarily contend that Peirce, were he to have lived for another century,
would have embraced the transhumanist label. We
contend, rather, that certain of his philosophical views are well aligned with
and support some key transhumanist ideas, so that it
might reasonably be supposed that he would have embraced some current transhumanist thought (and added to it). In section 1., we
explain how the pursuit of artificial
cognitive enhancement is required by Peirce’s accounts of truth and inquiry. In
section 2., we examine Peirce’s metaphysics of cognition and how, based upon
that metaphysics, our cognition can be directly enhanced by a wide range of
technologies (including computers or “logical machines”). Finally, in section 3.,
we link several passages in Peirce’s work concerning God and the ethical summum bonum to show
how the transformation of humans into posthumans
would seem to be, on his view, a fundamental ethical priority. 1. Peircean truth and posthuman
knowledge Peirce’s
identification of truth with “the opinion which is fated to be ultimately
agreed to by all who investigate” (W3:237, 1878) –
or
with “the predestined result to which sufficient inquiry would ultimately lead”
(CP 5.494, 1907) – is controversial. In response to the claim
that there would be such a “final opinion” or final result of inquiry if it
continued indefinitely, Bertrand Russell (1939, 146) asks a series of skeptical
questions: “Is this an empirical generalization from the history of research?
Or is it an optimistic belief in the perfectibility of man? Does it contain any
element of prophecy, or is it a merely hypothetical statement of what would
happen if men of science grew continually cleverer?” Another problem concerns
how a “final opinion” could constitute
the truth of a proposition; for even if a proposition’s being accepted as part
of such an opinion is a sufficient condition for its truth, to many
philosophers it could hardly be a necessary one. Contrary
to Russell, Peirce’s analysis of truth is not a “rash assertion” (1939, 146).
Peirce has deep theoretical reasons for analyzing truth in terms of a final
opinion, though his analysis does contain elements of empirical generalization
and prophecy. In his
seminal 1878 Popular Science Monthly
paper “How to Make Our Ideas Clear,” Peirce derives this analysis of truth by
applying his rule for attaining the third (and highest) grade of clearness in
our conceptions – what came to be called the “pragmatic maxim” –
so
that truth as the final opinion is
supposed to be our clearest conception of truth. But it is mainly in writings
of the 1900s that it becomes especially clear how the concept of the final
opinion is supposed to be our clearest concept of truth. In these writings we
find that, on the second grade of
clearness, a proposition is true if and only if it corresponds to its object.6 But, Peirce asks, “what does this correspondence or
reference of the sign, to its object, consist in?” (CP 5.553,
1906). His answer seems to be that it consists in a dynamical process
that over time would tend toward a
state of ideal stability or equilibrium between the interpreter of the sign and
its object (this ideal state being “the final opinion”). Though at
some places Peirce writes as if there would be a distinct final opinion for
every question (e.g, CP 8.43, 1885), he generally supposes
that there would be one final
opinion: the opinion that perfectly represents all reality external to the opinion or representation itself. This
is apparent in his original 1878 paper. For reasons that we’ll return to, only
as a whole could our beliefs attain an ideal stability with external reality.
Moreover, while Peirce holds that our clearest conception of reality is as the object of the final opinion, which
entails that there is no reality other than that which would be represented in
the final opinion, this does not entail that only at the final opinion is anything real. On its second grade of
clearness, reality is “that whose characters are independent of what anyone
thinks them to be” (CP 5.405, 1878); and, on the second grade, truth is a
certain correspondence between a representation and something that exists
independently of any representation of it. But it is
precisely this idea of reality as mind-independent that leads Peirce to the
analysis of truth as the final opinion. In “Some Consequences of Four
Incapacities” (1868), he argues that the mind-independence conception arises in
us when “we discover that there was an unreal, an illusion; that is, when we
first corrected ourselves” (W3:239). We discover that
reality is not simply whatever we might expect or want it to be, but is,
instead, a vast “non-ego” that incessantly clashes with our desires and
expectations. When reality disappoints our expectations, often we suppose that
we made some error and we attempt to correct ourselves (that is, if we are not
in a state of denial). Peirce calls the deliberate attempt to self-correct inquiry; and, on his view, the mind is
essentially a self-correcting system. What he calls “the law of mind” is a tendency
to develop habits of thought and belief that are better adapted to achieving a
certain end – namely, the
avoidance of disappointment by means of the use of things as signs. The theoretical final result of
this tendency would be an ideal stability between our use of signs and our
perceptual and behavioral interactions with objects. At that stage, there would
no longer be any need to self-correct. It is precisely in this sense that we
would achieve a sort of “complete knowledge” of external reality. There would
be nothing left for mind to know except
itself (for each representation of itself would introduce a new
representation to represent the previous one, ad infinitum).7 Whether
or not we make a deliberate attempt to self-correct, our inherent disposition
to self-correct would eventually compel us to believe the truth. Peirce writes
that even “the most pigheaded and passionate of men who has sworn by all the
gods that he never will allow himself to believe the earth is round” will
“surely come to and rest in the truth about the form of the earth” – that is,
if we “give him time enough, and cram that time with experience in the
pertinent sphere” (CP 7.78, c.1905). But so long as something remains unknown,
the process of self-correction continues. Indeed, knowing that there may remain
something unknown can cause doubt, as we might not know whether that unknown
might affect the justification of a given belief. Thus, any belief fails to
achieve ideal equilibrium with external reality if some part of it remains
unknown. The truth of any belief, then, depends on its being held alongside
other true beliefs; and the pursuit of the truth on any question is the pursuit
of all truth –
the
pursuit of the final opinion.8
Peirce’s account
of the deliberate level of the self-corrective process –
i.e.
inquiry –
makes
the most direct contribution to transhumanist
thinking. While in his 1877–78 papers he
argues that the goal of any sincere inquiry is truth,9 in works of the 1900s Peirce
explicates his general normative theory according to which truth is the
ultimate aim of inquiry, such that
the adoption of truth as its aim is constitutive of any genuine inquiry. Since
the ideal stability of belief is achieved only in toto, then the goal of any inquiry can
be none other than the final opinion. The final opinion is what all rational
inquirers must aim to achieve. On
Peirce’s account, then, not only is it logically rational to pursue this stage
of perfect cognition or ideally stable belief, it is logically irrational not to pursue it (though
under many circumstances it might not be ethical
to pursue it). Here a quintessential transhumanist
idea emerges from Peirce: the idea that we
ought to try to achieve a posthuman stage of
knowledge. As a perfect stage of knowledge, the final opinion may also be
described as a posthuman stage of knowledge –
that
is, on the assumption that humans in
their current form are incapable of indefinitely approaching the final
opinion. There are some indications that Peirce himself held this assumption. For
example, he consistently argues that science thus far is little more than the
development of instincts limited by the needs of evolution (e.g., CP 1.118,
5.586, 6.491, 7.508). Indeed, he suggests that all knowledge possessed by current humans is built upon
biologically based instincts that will need to cease “as we penetrate further
and further from the surface of nature” (CP 7.508, c.1898). Peirce thus expresses
the idea that humans may eventually need to change fundamentally in order to
advance any further in their knowledge. Nonetheless,
it is irrelevant whether Peirce believed that humans are incapable of
understanding nature outside of the “moderate-sized specimens of dry goods” of
their ecological niche (Austin 1964, 8). On his theory, it is true that if current humans are incapable of indefinitely
approaching the final opinion, then it is logically rational for them to pursue
the enhancements by which they could become so capable. Transhumanists
generally assume that there are some realities that are inaccessible to humans
given their biological limitations; and this assumption is both intuitive and
empirically supportable. The fact
that there is so much we know to be cognitively inaccessible to other animals
is often used to support the claim that there is probably much that is
inaccessible to current humans. Also, there seem to be realities open to
animals that are not open to humans – at the least, facts about
“what it is like” to be other animals
(i.e., facts about their subjective experience).10 Indeed, even if basic physics
is nearing “completion” (a proposition many view as highly doubtful), there
still may be facts about subjective experiences that we cannot represent in our
current biological form. Bostrom assumes at least
this much, but he thinks it is safe to assume that there are realities
accessible only to posthumans: creatures with
cognitive and sensory powers that far surpass those of any human. He offers the
following diagram to illustrate this idea:11 It is
possible that there are realities inaccessible even to posthumans,
and Bostrom represents that in this diagram. Facts
about the subjective experience of animals, including current humans, might be
among them. Although Peirce holds that all reality would be accessible to the
being or beings that achieve the final opinion, he can allow that at least current humans are limited in terms of
the realities that are accessible to them.12 Upon the
assumption that some realities are inaccessible to current humans, a simple
argument supporting the creation of superhuman cognition emerges from Peirce’s
theory of truth: 1.
At the
final opinion, everything real is represented.13 2.
It is
likely that reality exceeds what is within the cognitive grasp of humans given our
current biological limitations. 3.
Thus, it
is likely that the final opinion can be indefinitely approached only by some
intelligence surpassing current human limitations. Not only
is this argument implied by Peirce’s descriptive and normative accounts of
truth (in connection with his belief that reality may far exceed what we can
currently fathom), it also accords with his own optimism about the promises of
technology, including its promises of enhancing our abilities to acquire
knowledge. Peirce’s
optimism about what can be known (given enough time) shows clearly in his
response to “the problem of buried secrets.” This is the problem that some
“minute facts of history,” such as the precise history of the first
self-replicating molecules on Earth, seem impossible to know. His response
takes the form a rhetorical question: if inquiry “were to go on for a million,
or a billion, or any number of years you please, how is it possible to say that
there is any question which might not ultimately be solved” – especially, he
says, “given the activity of the last hundred?” (CP 5.409,
1878). More specially, he opines that the potential of science is
limitless: “Give science only a hundred more centuries of increase in
geometrical progression, and she may be expected to find that the sound waves
of Aristotle’s voice have somehow recorded themselves” (CP 5.542, 1902).14 Peirce
does not bet that any question will
be answered, as a matter of necessity. He asserts only that any question can and would be answered, so long as it is coherent and given enough time
and experience. Further,
Peirce was deeply impressed with the technological advancements achieved by his
time: “Modern science, with its microscopes and its telescopes, with its
chemistry and electricity, and with its entirely new appliances of life, has
put us into quite another world; almost as much so as if it had transported our
race to another planet” (CP 5.513). He recognizes and values how instruments
such as microscopes and telescopes afford us “recondite experiences” (CP 8.110,
1900) that advance us toward truth. Familiar with the work of Charles Babbage
(1791–1871) and others (see CP 2.56, 1902
and 4.611, 1908), Peirce understood the potential of calculating machines to
perform logical inferences, and he may have been the first to recognize the
potential of machines literally to think. In his 1887 article “Logical
Machines,” he comments: “Precisely how much of the business of thinking a
machine could possibly be made to perform, and what part of it must be left to
a living mind, is a question not without conceivable practical importance” (NEM
3: 625–32). In 1902, he considers the
possibility that such instruments could even have souls, given that they could
think (CP 2.56). Though he concludes that logical machines do not have souls –
at
least the logical machines conceivable in his time –
he
clearly considers whether they do to be a reasonable question. It is
hard to imagine, then, that Peirce would not see it as logically rational for
us to modify ourselves through applied science or to engineer some form of superintelligence, if
doing so is necessary for the indefinite community of inquirers to continue to
advance toward the final opinion. Since truth as the final opinion is the
constitutive aim of any genuine inquiry, it is thus instrumentally rational for
inquirers to enhance themselves artificially, if doing so is necessary or is
simply the most expeditious way to advance. Thus, combining this with the
notion that some realities are inaccessible to current humans, we obtain the
following argument: 1. All
reality is knowable only through cognitive abilities that exceed those of
current humans. 2.
If all reality is knowable only through
superhuman cognitive abilities, then we ought to try to engineer those
abilities. 3. Therefore,
we ought to try to engineer superhuman cognitive abilities. This
argument also implies that it might be rational to create a form of superintelligence that is not continuous with current humans, or that does not emerge from
direct enhancement of current humans. Peirce views the approach toward the
final opinion as contingent upon, not the survival of the human race in particular,
but the survival of the “indefinite community” of inquirers (e.g., W2:271, 1869; CP 2.654, 1878). He declares that “interest in
an indefinite community” and “hope in the unlimited continuance of intellectual
activity” are “indispensable requirements of logic” (CP 2.655).15 But if
the enhancement of current humans is a means of advancing inquiry generally, we
should aim to develop the technologies by which we could enhance our own
cognitive abilities. On Peirce’s view, by the first years of the twentieth century,
we had already developed technologies by which our minds are not only enhanced,
but are also externalized –
in
that parts of our cognitive processes take place outside our skulls. 2. Peirce’s external mind The locus classicus
for contemporary discussions of the “extended mind” remains Clark and Chalmers’
1998 argument for active externalism.
They argue against the “hegemony of skin and skull” in favor of cognitive
agents that are not only embodied, but also embedded
within external contexts that, at minimum, support cognition. In a riff on
another pragmatist, Hilary Putnam, Clark and Chalmers summarize their argument
as follows: If, as we confront some task, a part of the world functions as a process which, were it done in the head, we would have no
hesitation in recognizing as part of the cognitive process, then that part of
the world is (so we claim) part of the cognitive process. Cognitive processes ain’t (all) in the head! (1998, 8) This view
is called “active externalism” because it goes beyond externalism regarding
mental contents, which Clark and Chalmers see as having only a passive effect
on cognition, and instead makes central a coupling of organism and environment
“that can be seen as a cognitive system in its own right” (1998, 8). To make
this plausible, they introduce a thought experiment involving Otto, a person
with Alzheimer’s disease who relies upon a notebook to supplement, or even
replace, his memory. Without his notebook, he is prone to cognitive failures,
but with it he functions as well as a “normal” cognitive agent. This suggests
that Otto’s very self is extended: “The information in Otto’s notebook, for
example, is a central part of his identity as a cognitive agent. What this
comes to is that Otto himself is best
regarded as an extended system, a coupling of biological organism and external
resources” (1998, 18). What is
true of Otto is true of many of us, especially in light of the proliferation of
cognitive prostheses – i.e., smartphones – since
Clark and Chalmers’ original paper. While our focus is on the technological
extension and improvement of the human central to transhumanism,
we also want to note that the “external resources” mentioned by Clark and
Chalmers sometimes include other organisms: What about socially extended cognition? Could my mental states be
constituted by the states of other thinkers? We see no reason why not, in
principle. In an unusually interdependent couple, it is entirely possible that
one partner’s beliefs will play the same sort of role for the other as the
notebook plays for Otto. (1998, 17) However,
why think this is limited to “unusually” interdependent couples? As Daniel
Wegner has argued, we are enmeshed in a variety of transactive memory systems that, while perhaps idealized by a couple that
literally finishes each other’s thoughts, may involve looser social ties, such
as between professor and student.16 Wegner (1986) also acknowledges that artifacts
contribute to our transactive memory systems, insofar
as we delegate much of our memory storage to external locations: As an example of this, suppose that one
encodes this book in memory. To encode it internally requires learning some
sort of label (e.g., the book’s title), and then memorizing the rest of it from
cover to cover. To encode it externally also requires learning the label, but
then only calls for learning where the book can be found. (Wegner 1986, 189) Thus,
whether artifact or person, our cognition reaches into the world. Significantly,
Peirce anticipated these forms of active and transactive
externalism, and thereby provided a potential transhumanist ontology in addition to an epistemology and ethics.
In 1868’s “Some Consequences of Four Incapacities” and elsewhere, Peirce argues
for “scholastic realism”, the position that generals or universals (e.g., red, man)
and not only particulars (e.g., this red,
Aristotle) have a real existence (CP
5.312).17
This realism leads to the position that “the mind is a sign developing
according to the laws of inference” and therefore, perhaps bizarrely, there are
only relative differences between a person and a word (CP 5.313). In short,
people and words are both signs, distinct from their physical manifestations,
whether my body before lunch and after, or in thousands of different books: It is hard for man to understand this, because he persists in
identifying himself with his will, his power over the animal organism, with
brute force. Now the organism is only an instrument of thought. But the
identity of a man consists in the consistency
of what he does and thinks, and consistency is the intellectual character
of a thing; that is, is its expressing something. (CP 5.315) This
leads Peirce to claim nearly 40 years later, in 1905’s “What Pragmatism Is,” that “the man’s circle of society (however widely or
narrowly this phrase may be understood), is sort of a loosely compacted person,
in some respects of higher rank than the person of an individual organism” (CP
5.421). Thus, Peirce seems to be a clear predecessor to the tradition of
socially extended transactive cognition of Clark,
Chalmers, and Wegner, among others. He even has his own take on the “hegemony
of skull and skin,” as evinced by the following: Why we used to read that the soul resides in a little organ of the
brain no bigger than a pin’s head. Most anthropologists now more rationally say
that the soul is either spread over the whole body or is all in all and all in
every part. But are we shut up in a box
of flesh and blood? When I communicate my thought and my sentiments to a
friend with whom I am in full
sympathy, so that my feelings pass into him and I am conscious of what he feels, do I not live in his brain as
well as in my own – most literally? (CP.
7.591; emphasis added)18 Peirce
goes further to argue that cognition is extended not only socially, but also artifactually and technologically. He remarks that “it is
much more true that the thoughts of a living writer are in any printed copy of
his book than that they are in his brain.” This comes within the context of a
distinction he makes between mind and consciousness, where consciousness “is
nothing but the inward aspect of things, while mind on the contrary is
essentially an external phenomenon” (CP 7.364, 1902). By “external” he does not
mean only “external to the skull,” but he is clear that mind can be partly external to the skull.
This is shown not only by his comments about an author’s thoughts being more in
his book than in his brain, but also by his general argument concerning the
localization of the mind: A psychologist cuts out a lobe of my brain and then, when I find I
cannot express myself, he says, “You see, your faculty of language was
localized in that lobe.” No doubt it was; and so, if he had filched my
inkstand, I should not have been able to continue my discussion until I had got
another. Yea, the very thoughts would not come to me. So my faculty of
discussion is equally localized in my inkstand. (CP 7.366, 1905) Peirce
insists that the inkstand is not only a means of communicating his thoughts,
but is also an engine or co-producer of his thoughts. As Skagestad
puts it, “thoughts come to him in and through the act of writing, so that
having writing implements is a condition for having certain thoughts” (1999,
551). Though a condition for thought is not the same as an embodiment or a
localization of thought, Peirce’s point is precisely that if our best reason
for locating the mind in the brain is that brain processes and organs are
necessary for thought, then we have the same reason to locate the mind outside
of the brain, in objects like books, inkstands, and, in the early twenty-first
century, in smartphones, personal computers and the World Wide Web. Finally,
Peirce makes an intriguing suggestion in one of his accounts of cognition as a
process of observation and experimentation “which is substantially the same
process whether it be performed with physical apparatus such as the chemist
uses or with an apparatus of diagrams of our own creation, such as the
mathematician employ” (CP 7.276). These “diagrams of our own creation” can be
written equations or figures, or simply imagined
ones. Thus, for Peirce, we can reason through
a physical apparatus, such as a chemistry set, in effectively the same sense in
which we reason through our own brains. Peirce’s
own extended mind thesis thus allows for more forms of cognitive enhancement
than the old localized(-in-the-brain) view. Our
increasing ability to interface our brains with our computers will almost
surely enhance our ability to perform many different cognitive tasks. We
already interface our brains with our computers using our eyes and our hands,
and this gives us vastly more powerful ways to enhance our ability to perform
mathematical, linguistic, and knowledge-retrieval tasks.19 Further, Peirce argues that the growth
of science is due, in large part, to the development of technologies to expand
our biological faculties. He himself worked for the U.S. Coast Geodetic Survey,
and developed an improved pendulum for measuring minute variations in gravity
(CP 7.16). In the century of change after his death, we have already moved far
beyond the microscopes, pendulums, and telescopes that Peirce thought had put
us into another world of ability and knowledge. However,
why do we necessarily want to enhance our abilities? On Peirce’s view, it is
not simply to expedite our approach to the final opinion. It is also to
expedite our approach to a state that we might call posthumanity. 3. Peirce’s summum bonum and the
posthuman realm In
section 1., we argued that, upon Peirce’s account, it is logically or epistemically rational for human inquirers to enhance their
cognitive abilities through technological means in order to surpass biological
barriers to approaching the final opinion or truth. But while it is logically or epistemically rational to do
so, there are many circumstances under which it would not be practical, morally
correct, or rational in an all-things-considered sense, to enhance or to
promote such enhancement. For instance, the development of certain
relevant technologies may pose a significant risk to the welfare of millions.
Many transhumanist thinkers, notably Bostrom (2014), have investigated and warned of such risks.
But Peirce’s moral philosophy suggests that, while these risks are morally
serious, we have a fundamental moral obligation to pursue enhancements of our
cognitive, social, and physical capacities. On his view, it seems, our
fundamental moral imperative is to strive toward a sort of Godhood, where this imperative includes our fundamental epistemic imperative
to strive toward a Godlike stage of knowledge (i.e., the final opinion). Here
there is a distinct correspondence between Peircean
ethics and Bostrom-style transhumanism.
Peirce’s summum bonum bears
striking similarity to what Bostrom (2005b) declares
to be the core transhumanist ideal: the exploration of the posthuman
realm. At some point in their approach toward the final opinion, enhanced
human inquirers will have enhanced so far that little or no human biology will
remain essential to their continued existence. They will have become posthumans. Thus, approaching the final opinion implies
approaching what Bostrom calls the posthuman realm. By the “posthuman realm” Bostrom means
the “modes of being” occupied by creatures that have physical, cognitive, and
moral capacities that far exceed those of current humans. Potential posthumans include descendants of humans and, most
optimistically, former humans who have attained such extraordinary capacities
over time. He does not assume that there is any sharp transition from human to transhuman (or enhanced human) to posthuman:
a posthuman may just be a human that is so enhanced,
perhaps shedding all of its original biology, that it becomes unclear what
meaning there is in calling it “human.”20 The exploration of the posthuman realm, then,
would be the exploration of what is accessible with such capacities. It would
be precipitous to place metaphysical limitations on this exploration, other
than that it must involve the exploration of more than what is accessible to
current humans.21 But for Bostrom, it potentially
involves the exploration of other values,
as current human values might not be among the values of posthumans.
Our current values would be more deeply explored, as Bostrom
points out, but no specific values or motivations can be established a priori
for posthumans. Peirce
always considered himself first and foremost a logician. But at least from the
late 1870s onward, ethical matters were never very far from his mind. He says
that he began taking a serious interest in moral philosophy in 1883 (CP 5.129),
which was around the time he wrote a review of Josiah Royce’s The Religious Aspect of Philosophy
(1885), in which he criticizes Royce’s distinction between “moral realism” and
“moral idealism” and seems to defend a sort of synthesis of the two (CP 8.45–52). While in his famous 1898 Cambridge
Conferences lectures, Peirce remarks that ethics is a “useless” science, by
1902 he begins to place far more systematic importance on ethics. He declares
that ethics is a positive science or
a science concerning real facts, and he develops a general value theory on
which the summum bonum or the
highest ideal of human action incorporates the highest logical ideal: the final opinion. In his
1903 Harvard lectures (and in other writings around that time),22 Peirce
identifies logic as a normative science,
where normative science generally concerns “the laws of the relation of
phenomena to ends” (EP2:197). As such, logic concerns the relation of phenomena
to truth –
the
ultimate end of inquiry (EP 2:200). Peirce’s use of “logic” as the name for an
area of inquiry includes what (within the last century of mostly Anglophone
philosophy) has gone under the headings of “epistemology” and “philosophy of
science,” as well as “philosophy of language.” Peirce also considers ethics a normative science, where ethics
concerns “those things whose end lie in action” (EP 2:200). Ethics “is the
study of what ends of action we are deliberately prepared to adopt” –
or
of what is “morally good” (CP 5.130). It is not only the study of the
conformity of action to an end or ideal, but is the “theory of the ideal
itself, the nature of the summum bonum”
(EP2:377, 1906). Note, however, that Peirce thinks
that “the morally good appears as a particular species of the esthetically
good” (CP 5.130), because the moral good must be “admirable in itself” and
esthetics is the study of what is admirable in itself. And just as the moral
good (the summum bonum) is a
species of the esthetic good, so the logical good (truth) is, on his view, a
species of the moral good (CP 5.130). He writes that truth is a “phase” of the summum bonum; and
for this reason “the logician ought to recognize what our ultimate aim [of
action] is” (CP 1.611, 1903).23 But what
exactly does Peirce take to be the summum bonum? What he says about it is rather cryptic and a little
sparse. He writes that, for the pragmaticist,24 the summum bonum is the “process of evolution
whereby the existent comes more and more to embody [reasonable] generals,” where
at higher stages this “evolution takes place more and more largely through
self-control” (CP 5.433, 1905). Many scholars identify this “process of
evolution” with what he elsewhere (and a little earlier) refers to as the
development of “concrete reasonableness” (CP 5.3, 1902; see Potter 1967, Herdy 2014, Atkins 2016), which involves “the becoming
governed by laws” – that is, bringing order to chaos. Laws are
the generals which the existent grows to embody; and while, at earlier stages,
the formation of laws is not necessarily guided by any intelligence (as is the
case with basic physical laws), at later stages the formation of laws occurs
through intelligent self-controlled processes (as is the case with social or
institutional laws ‒ this is not to imply that all
institutional laws should be thought of as intelligent!). But the process
cannot end with the formation of institutional laws, for there is far more room
for growth of order in the universe. Peirce’s idea seems to be that the development of order across all
reality would become guided by intelligent processes. This implies an
intelligent creator – or, perhaps, an intelligent re-creator. In 1905,
Peirce writes that “I look upon creation as going on and I believe that such
vague ideas as we can have of the power of creation is best identified with the
idea of theism” (CP 8.138fn4, 1905;
our emphasis). Continuing in the same note, he tells us that
“the [ultimate] ideal would be to be fulfilling our appropriate offices in the
work of creation,” where “every man” should “feel that he is doing what God
made him in order that he should do”. Peirce seems committed to the idea of a
pre-creation God, as opposed to a created God that takes over the process of
creation. And there are clear grounds for regarding him as a traditional theist
(for more on Peirce’s complex conception of God, see Delaney 1992, Mahowald 1976, and Orange 1985). However,
Peirce complicates his theism at several points in his writings. A stunning
example is the following passage, where he cautions against claiming that God exists in any “wooden sense” and
hints at a God that “self-reproduces”: We cannot possibly put ourselves in God’s shoes, even so far as to say
in any definite wooden sense that God is.
I only mean that the purpose of creation as it must appear to us in our highest
approaches to an understanding of it, is to make an answering mind. It is God’s
movement toward self-reproduction. And when I say that God is, I mean that the conception of a God is the highest flight
toward an understanding of the original of the whole physico-psychical
universe that we can make. (R 1334, 1905) Peirce
says that the “purpose of creation” is to make an “answering mind”, and that to
make an answering mind is “God’s movement toward self-reproduction.” The
creation of an “answering mind” would seem to be the achievement of a mind that
answers all questions or achieves the final opinion (as one “perfection” among
others). It seems that, based on this passage, God’s purpose behind creation is
to produce a new God, or perhaps to “renew Himself.” If this is supposed to
occur through the self-controlled and intelligent conduct of created beings,
then the creation of a new God is the
summum bonum of
intelligent created beings like us. Moreover,
Peirce suggests that we should not necessarily look to God for help in pursuit
of this end. We should pursue it on our own. He remarks that “[l]ike a good teacher, [God] is
engaged in detaching us from a false dependence upon him” (CP 6.507). At some
places Peirce speaks of a “love of God”; and in the 1885 review of Royce, he
identifies love of God with love of an “ideal and divine humanity” (CP 8.47).
He argues that this love develops from a “collective egoism” (an in-group bias)
and grows into a “sympathy” for the “ocean of human
misery” before “finally, steadying itself by the conception of an ideal
humanity and a divine providence” (CP 8.49). If this love of “an ideal and
divine humanity” develops from a sympathy for all
human suffering, presumably it is a love, or a hope, for a humanity that will become ideal and divine, and does
not suffer. It would seem, then, that this love for God is essentially a desire
for humans to overcome those conditions that limit their freedom and cause them
suffering. To be
logical, Peirce writes, “men should not be selfish” (CP 2.654, 1878); and this
is because the “ideal perfection of knowledge” is the goal, not of an
individual, but of the entire “community of inquirers” (W2:271,
1869). We should not desire that just humans
approach the final opinion. As Peirce says, we must extend this community of
inquirers to “all races of beings with whom we can come in immediate or mediate
intellectual relation” (CP 2.654, 1878). And so, as our ultimate logical end,
truth or the final opinion, is a phase of the summum bonum, the pursuit of it implies the
pursuit of an ideal and divine community – one that is not limited by
natural biological conditions. Peirce
thus anticipates Hopkins (2008), who writes: “these elements of a transhumanist moral vision – namely that we alter ourselves
in order to pursue the humanly imagined and unimagined good that we cannot
achieve given our current limitations, only speaks to the grander picture, the
ultimate motivation, the search for the summum bonum of the fully sapient creature” (Hopkins 2008, 6).
Of course, Peirce never says explicitly that we should enhance our basic
capacities through technological means – a task that was practically
unheard of during his time. While he attended to the ways we already think in
and through our environment, including artifacts, he did not call for the
invention of better inkstands or typewriters. Nevertheless, the idea that we
should enhance our basic capacities is strongly implied by his normative philosophy,
or by his conceptions of the ultimate end of all inquiry, and, more generally,
the ultimate end of all conduct.25 One of
the central points of Bostrom’s work on transhumanist values is that the posthuman
might explore values that are inaccessible to current humans for one reason or
another. We find a not-so-dissimilar idea in Peirce.26 The summum bonum – the
growth of concrete reasonableness through a self-controlled approach toward a
God-like stage of being – is the moral good for current humans; but the moral good
is, on his view, a species of the esthetically good, which is anything that is
admirable-in-itself, including things that are not directly goods of action.
“Beauty” might be an example of this, as beauty is not (or is not strictly) a
good of action. Indeed, the approach toward Godhood or toward the posthuman may be the summum bonum because it involves the
realization of all that is inherently admirable or valuable. Peirce
offers a consistent vision of the human, a natural being, both limited by
bodies and already transcending them, on a trajectory of communal inquiry that
is also a project of self-overcoming in order to know all that is knowable, and
to experience all that can be experienced. Thus, Peirce deserves to be regarded
as one of the great philosophical predecessors to contemporary transhumanism. Notes 1. We would like to thank the participants of “Science and Values in Peirce and Dewey: A Conference inHonourof Angus Kerr-Lawson” at the University of Waterloo, especially the organizer, ShannonDea, for an initial opportunity to present these ideas. 2.
Bostrom also traces transhumanist
thought to some ancient schools, myths, and literature, such as the Epic of Gilgamesh (c. 2000 B.C.). 3. As the name of a distinct
intellectual movement, the term “transhumanism”
originates with Max More and was first used by a circle of associates in
California that also included FM-2030 (originally Fereidoun
M. Esfandiary), and Natasha Vita-More. Although, in
More’s original publication, “transhumanism” is
defined as “a class of philosophies that seek to guide us towards
a posthuman
condition” (1990, 6), Julian Huxley had previously characterized transhumanism as the belief that “the human species can, if
it wishes, transcend itself not just sporadically, an individual here in one
way, an individual there in another way, but in its entirety, as humanity”
(1957, 17). More does not appear to have borrowed the term from Huxley.
Nonetheless, the latter’s conception of transhumanism
would seem to fall within the class of philosophies that More calls “transhumanism.” 4. We have found no evidence that Peirce
had a direct influence on the origins of transhumanism,
including the term. However, Harrison and Wolyniak
2015 argue, contra Bostrom, that Huxley did not coin the term. Instead, they
find it in Dante’s Paradiso,
which seemed to influence a 1940 reference to “Paul’s Transhumanism”
by W. D. Lighthall in his “The Law of Cosmic
Evolutionary Adaptation.” Lighthall was also influenced by a fellow Canadian philosopher, Bruce W. Brotherston, referencing him in a 1926 article on “superpersonality.” Brotherston
knew the classical pragmatists, and even published an article on Peirce in
1939. However, the trail turns cold here with the slimmest of possible
influence. Indirectly, Peirce’s potential influence via semiotics (especially cybersemiotics) is too immense to review here; see Brier
1999 for one example. 5. As used here, “epistemic rationality” applies to
deliberate actions that would maximize the realization of epistemic ideals such
as the attainment of truth, either by increasing the likelihood of achieving an
epistemic ideal, by expediting the time it would take to achieve an epistemic
ideal, or by realizing something that approximates closer to an epistemic
ideal. In the context of the work of Charles S. Peirce, “logical rationality”
will be used as a synonym. On his usage, “logic” concerns representation,
reasoning, inquiry, and knowledge. For a full account of Peirce’s use of “logic,”
see Wilson 2016, 34–35. 6.
In 1903, Peirce wrote: “Every man is fully satisfied that there is such a thing
as truth, or he would not ask any question. That
truth consists in a conformity to something independent of his thinking it to
be so, or of any man’s opinion on that subject” (CP 5.211; Peirce’s emphasis). 7.
As Wilson (2016) explains, a
complete representation of reality, then, would really represent every real
representation. This leads to a regress: any representation A is represented by
B, which in turn is represented by C, ad infinitum. … But this infinite regress
occurs only with respect to self-referential knowledge or representation, which
leaves room for the possibility of an actual state at which all that remains to
be represented are the representations of the final opinion itself. (256–57) Wilson
points out other possible problems with conceiving Peirce’s “final opinion” as
an achievable state, as opposed to be a purely theoretical (unachievable)
limit. But so long as reality external to
the representational process itself is finite, Peirce’s “final opinion” is an
achievable point. If external reality is not finite, then the semiotic process
cannot be described as tending toward even a limit. 8. That
is, the pursuit of truth is the pursuit of “all truth” about external reality;
see the previous note. 9.
In the first of his 1877–1878 Popular Science Monthly series of
articles, “The Fixation of Belief,” Peirce argues that the “settlement of
opinion” is the sole aim of any inquiry (W 3:248), and in the second of the
series, “How to Make Our Ideas Clear,” he identifies the “opinion which is
fated to be ultimately agreed to by all who investigate” as our clearest
conception of truth. 10. The
belief that there are such facts about subjective experience springs from such
famous “knowledge arguments” as those given by Nagel 1974 and Jackson 1982.
Jackson’s famous argument involves a scientist who never sees colors but learns
all there is to know about the physical universe from a black and white screen
in a black and white room. Upon being released, she sees colors, and the
intuition is that she learns something new. Some maintain that she learns something
new, but not a different type of fact: a different “way” of knowing a certain
fact (Horgan 1984); others maintain that she only
acquires new non-propositional
knowledge, acquaintance-knowledge and knowledge-how, and that therefore she is
not learning any new facts (Lewis 1988; Conee 1994). 11. Source
of diagram: Bostrom 2005b. Permission
to reproduce diagram granted on June 15, 2017. 12.
There are at least two other passages in which Peirce argues that our science
is limited by our natural instincts: (1) “In the first place all that science
has done is to study those relations between objects which were brought into
prominence and conceiving which we had been endowed with some original
knowledge in two instincts – the instinct of
feeding, which brought with it elementary knowledge of mechanical forces,
space, etc., and the instinct of breeding, which brought with it elementary
knowledge of psychical motives, of time, etc.” (CP 1.118, c.1896); and (2) “The
instincts connected with the need of nutrition have furnished all animals with
some virtual knowledge of space and of force, and made them applied physicists.
The instincts connected with sexual reproduction have furnished all animals at
all like ourselves with some virtual comprehension of
the minds of other animals of their kind, so that they are applied psychists. Now not only our accomplished science, but even
our scientific questions have been pretty exclusively limited to the
development of those two branches of natural knowledge” (CP 5.586, 1898). 13. More specifically, at the
final opinion, everything that is real and
external to the representation (the final opinion) itself is represented. See
note 7. 14. Also
see CP 2.642, 1878, where Peirce suggests the possibility of learning more
about Napoleon Bonaparte: It may be that, at the time of his career, events were being recorded
in some way not now dreamed of, that some ingenious creature on a neighboring
planet was photographing the earth, and that these pictures on a sufficiently
large scale may some time come into our possession, or that some mirror upon a
distant star will, when the light reaches it, reflect the whole story back to
earth. Never mind how improbable these suppositions are; everything
which happens is infinitely improbable. 15. Peirce
argues: Our
perversity and that of others may indefinitely postpone the settlement of
opinion; it might even conceivably cause an arbitrary proposition to be
universally accepted as long as the human race should last. Yet even that would
not change the nature of the belief, which alone could be the result of
investigation carried sufficiently far; and if, after the extinction of our
race, another should arise with faculties and disposition for investigation,
that true opinion must be the one which they would ultimately come to. (CP
5.408, 1878) 16. See
Wegner 1986, 189: In either case, one person has access to information in another’s
memory by virtue of knowing that the other person is a location for an item
with a certain label. This allows both people to depend on communication with
each other for the enhancement of their personal memory stores. At the same
time, however, this interdependence produces a knowledge-holding system that is
larger and more complex than either of the individuals’ own memory systems. 17. In later works, Peirce is more careful to
distinguish between existence and reality as modes of being, while still
holding that universals are real. For more on memory and Peirce’s pragmatism
and realism, see Brunson 2007. 18. As
“soul” is not a technical term for Peirce, we could readily replace it with
“mind” in this passage. In addition, there are some suggestions in Peirce
(e.g., CP 5.313, 7.592) that could support reinterpreting his views along the
lines of Floridi’s contention that personal identity is inherently informational –
see Floridi 2011, and also Fairbanks 1976. However,
we cannot develop this argument here. 19. As
Esposito argues: “In general, the newer sciences of cybernetics, bionics, and
ergonomics can perhaps give new vitality to [Peirce’s] synechistic
philosophy by refusing to take seriously, whether consciously or by
implication, essential mind/matter and natural/artificial distinctions” (1973,
76). Synechism
is Peirce’s name for “the tendency to regard everything as continuous” (CP
7.565). 20.
There may be physical and even psychological continuity between a human
and a posthuman. But the differences between a human
and a posthuman may exceed the differences between a
bacterium and a human; in that case, a whole new classification of lifeform (a kingdom) would be appropriate. Indeed, the
concept of the posthuman challenges our very
definition of “life.” 21.
One might attempt to place some metaphysical limitations on the posthuman realm through a priori reasoning (e.g., through
application of the principle of non-contradiction). But a fundamental
assumption of (Peircean) fallibilism
is that anything is epistemically possible: for any
proposition P that S thinks that she
knows, it is possible that S does not know that P (because not-P). This
is different from skepticism, which says that for any P that S thinks that she knows, S does not know that P. (Peircean) fallibilism does not rule out that S knows that P, or even that S knows that she knows
that P. It is the claim that any knowledge-claim could be false, so that,
for us, anything could be true or false in that sense. Posthumans
might be in a totally different epistemic situation. 22. For
instance, Peirce identifies logic as a normative science in the 1902
unpublished fragments of the “Minute
Logic” (e.g. CP 1.281, 1.575). 23. Peirce
adds that it is the business of “the moralist” to find out what our ultimate
aim is; but whatever the moralist finds it to be, “the logician has to accept
the teaching of ethics in this regard” (CP 1.611, 1903). 24. As is
often noted in works on Peirce, in 1905 Peirce adopted the term “pragmaticism” to distinguish his form of pragmatism from
others. By this point in his writings, his pragmatism or pragmaticism
was clearly a theory of conceptual representation –
and
not just a principle of analysis – of which he took his realism
about modality and universal as well as his “critical common-sensism” or his position on first principles to be
consequences (CP 5.439). 25. Perhaps
the closest he gets is the practical recommendation to constantly take notes: Moreover, procure, in lots of twenty thousand or more, slips of stiff
paper of the size of postcards, made up into pads of fifty or so. Have a pad
always about you, and note upon one of them anything worthy of note, the
subject being stated at the top and reference being made below to available
books or to your own note books. If your mind is
active, a day will seldom pass when you do not find a dozen items worth such
recording; and at the end of twenty years, the slips having been classified and
arranged and rearranged, from time to time, you will find yourself in
possession of an encyclopaedia adapted to your own
special wants. It is especially the small points that are thus to be noted; for
the large ideas you will carry in your head. (CP 4.597) This is
another case of extended memory, of course. 26. One
of Peirce’s innovations in logic is the invention of “existential graphs,” a
diagrammatic version of formal logic that he considered a superior form of
cognition: “A person who has learned to think in beta graphs has ideas of the
utmost clearness and precision which it is practically impossible to
communicate to the mind of a person who has not that advantage” (CP 4.150). References Atkins, R. K. 2016. Peirce and the conduct of life: Sentiment
and instinct in ethics and religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Austin, J. L. 1964. Sense and sensibilia,
ed. G. J. Warnock. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bostrom, N. 2005a. A history of transhumanist
thought. Journal of
Evolution and Technology 14(1): 1–25.
———. 2014. Superintelligence: Paths, dangers, strategies.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brier, S. 1999. Biosemiotics
and the foundations of cybersemiotics: Reconceptualizing the insights of ethology, second-order cybernetics,
and Peirce’s semiotics in biosemiotics to create a
non- Cartesian information science. Semiotica 127(1–4):
169–98. Brotherston, B. W.
1939. Firstness. Journal of Philosophy 36(20): 533–43. Brunson, D. 2007. Memory and Peirce’s pragmatism. Cognitio-Estudios: Revista eletrônica de filosofia Clark, A. and D. Chalmers. 1998. The extended mind.
Analysis 58(1):
7–19. Conee, E. 1994. Phenomenal knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72:
136–50. Delaney, C. F. 1992. Peirce on the hypothesis of God. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce
Society 28(4): 725–39. Esposito, J. L. 1973. Synechism, socialism,
and cybernetics. Transactions of
the Charles S. Peirce Fairbanks, M. 1976. Peirce
on man as a language: A textual interpretation. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce
Society 12(1): 18–32. Floridi, L. 2011. The informational nature of personal identity. Minds and Machines 21:
549–66. Harrison, P., and J. Wolyniak,
2015. The history of “transhumanism.” Notes and Queries 62: 465–67. Herdy, R. 2014. The origin and growth of Peirce’s ethics: A categorical
analysis. European Journal of Hopkins, P. 2008. A moral vision
for transhumanism. Journal of Evolution and Technology 19(1):
3–7. Huxley, J. 1951. Knowledge, morality, and destiny. Psychiatry 14: 129–51. ———. 1957. Transhumanism. In New bottles for new wine,
13–17.
London: Chatto & Windus. Jackson, F. 1982.
Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical
Quarterly 32: 127–36. Lewis, D. 1988. What experience
teaches. Proceedings of the Russellian Society 13:
29–57. Lighthall, W. D. 1926. Is superpersonality
the looked-for principle? Philosophical
Review 35(4): 360–65. ———. 1940.
The law of cosmic evolutionary adaptation: An interpretation of recent thought.
Royal Mahowald, M. 1976. Peirce’s concepts of God
and religion. Transactions of the
Charles S. Peirce More, M. 1990. Transhumanism:
Toward a futurist philosophy. Extropy
6: 6–12. More, M. 2013. The philosophy of transhumanism. In The transhumanist
reader, ed. M. More and N. Vita-More, 3–17. Chichester:
Wiley-Blackwell. Nagel, T. 1974. What is
it like to be a bat? Philosophical
Review 83: 435–50. Orange, D. M. 1984. Peirce’s conception of God: A developmental
study. Lubbock, TX: Institute for the Studies of Pragmaticism. Peirce, C. S. 1931–1958.
Collected papers of Charles S. Peirce,
ed. Charles Hartshorne, Paul Weiss, and Arthur Burks. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press. (Except where otherwise indicated, citations in the text
refer to the Collected Papers as CP followed
by volume and paragraph numbers, and, when known, date of composition.) ———. 1992, 1998. The essential Peirce. Vol. 1, ed. Nathan
House and Christian Kloesel; vol. 2, ed. the Peirce
Edition Project. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. (Cited in
the text as EP volume:page.) ———. 1982. Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A
chronological edition (6 vols. to date), general ed. Max H. Fisch. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. (Cited in
the text as W volume:page.) ———. 1976. The new elements of mathematics by Charles
S. Peirce, vols. 1, 2, 3.1, and 3.2, ed. Carolyn Eisele. The
Hague: Mouton Publishers. (Cited in the text as NEM volume:page.) Potter, V. 1967. Charles S. Peirce on norms and ideals.
Worcester, MA: University of Massachusetts Press. Russell, B. 1939. Dewey’s new logic. In The philosophy of John Dewey, ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp
and Lewis Edwin Hahn, 137–56. La Salle, IL: Open Court. Wegner, D. 1986. Transactive memory. In Theories
of group behavior, ed. B. Mullen and R. Goethals, 185–208. New York:
Springer-Verlag. Wilson, A. 2016. Peirce’s empiricism: Its roots and its
originality. Lanham, MD: Lexington. |