Forever and Again: Necessary Conditions for “Quantum
Immortality” and its Practical Implications Alexey Turchin Science for Life Extension Foundation Digital Immortality Now Journal of Evolution and Technology - Vol. 28 Issue 1 – December 2018 - pgs 31- 56 Abstract This article explores
theoretical conditions necessary for “quantum immortality” (QI) as well as its
possible practical implications. It is demonstrated that QI is a particular
case of “multiverse immortality” (MI), which is based on two main assumptions:
the very large size of the universe (not necessarily because of quantum
effects); and a copy-friendly theory of personal identity. It is shown that a
popular objection about lowering of the world-share (measure) of an observer in
the case of QI does not succeed, as the world-share decline could
be compensated by merging timelines for the simpler minds, and because some
types of personal preferences are not dependent on such changes. Despite large
uncertainty about the truth of MI, it has appreciable practical consequences for
some important outcomes like suicide and aging. The article demonstrates that
MI could be used to significantly increase the expected subjective probability
of success of risky life extension technologies, such as cryonics, but that it makes
euthanasia impractical because of the risk of eternal suffering. Euthanasia
should be replaced with cryothanasia, i.e. cryopreservation
after voluntary death. Another possible application of MI is as a last chance
to survive a global catastrophe. MI could be considered a Plan D for reaching
immortality, where Plan A consists of survival until the development of
beneficial Artificial Intelligence capable of fighting aging, Plan B employs cryonics,
and Plan C is digital immortality. Highlights · Quantum immortality (QI)
is a particular case of multiverse immortality (MI). · The validity of MI
depends on the size of the universe and the nature of personal identity, but is
still uncertain. · The counterargument of “world-share
decline” depends on the type of preferences and merging timelines. · MI greatly increases the
subjective chances of the success of cryonics, makes euthanasia impossible, but
favors cryothanasia. · MI is our last line of defense
against existential risks. Disclaimer:
Suicide will never be useful as an implication of QI: if QI is true, suicide will
probably result in a non-deadly serious injury, permanent brain damage, and
infinite suffering. Accordingly, the idea of QI is not an argument for suicide,
but is one of the strongest arguments against it. If you are interested in
suicide, seek professional psychological help. Warning: Memetic hazard for people who tend to react emotionally to
thought experiments! Abbreviations AI – Artificial Intelligence QS – Quantum suicide (or
quantum suicide thought experiment) QI – Quantum immortality MI – Multiverse immortality:
umbrella term for QI and big world immortality MWI – Many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics UDT – Updateless
Decision Theory 1. Introduction
The main idea behind quantum immortality (QI) is that
constant branching of the multiverse – according to the many-worlds
interpretation (MWI) of quantum mechanics – ensures the existence of timelines in
which a given observer will survive any dangerous situation. The idea was
suggested in the form of a quantum suicide (QS) thought experiment by Tegmark (1998) and others. Most scientists who have written about the idea of QI have
felt an obligation to disprove it (Randall 2004; Mallah
2009; Almond 2011a; Aranyosi 2012),1
in the same way as most authors try to disprove the notorious Doomsday argument
(Bostrom 1999), which is commonly interpreted as
supporting a pessimistic estimate of how long humanity will survive as a
species. Critics of QI do not analyze the implications if QI is true, and as result,
the possible practical consequences of the idea are underexplored. Quantum
immortality is closely related to the effective altruism circle of problems. If
QI is real, it follows that there is a possibility of infinite future suffering
for any sentient being (Aranyosi 2012), as it will
not be able to die, but will continue to age. So, QI is an s-risk. The concept of an s-risk was introduced by Max Daniel (2017)
to denote risks whose outcomes could include “suffering on an astronomical
scale, vastly exceeding all suffering that has existed on Earth so far.”2
In what follows, however, it will be
demonstrated that there is a way to prevent this s-risk for people who are currently
alive. This involves increasing their possible positive timelines, extending
into the infinite future, by signing up to cryonic suspension and storage.3 An
overview of the history of the idea of QI, its formalism, and its relation to
the idea of death is presented in Section 2. Section 3 is devoted to the
difference between QI and multiverse immortality (MI), and the conditions
necessary for them to be true are analyzed. Section 4 explains the possible bad
consequences of “natural” QI. In Section 5, QI is explored from the point of
view of decision theory, and the “measure decline” objection is analyzed.
Section 6 provides an overview of the practical applications of QI, including
overcoming the negative effects of natural QI via cryothanasia
(cryopreservation after voluntary death). 2. The nature and formalism of multiverse immortality
2.1 History of the ideaThe first stage of the concept that the infinite size
of the universe implies some form of immortality was the idea of so-called
eternal return, that is, the repeated appearance of the same observers. The earliest
versions of the eternal return theory appeared in ancient philosophy (Eliade 1949) and still attract interest today (Bergström
2012). Empedocles of Akragas
reportedly believed in the cyclic return of everything based on the
recombination of four elements, ensuring personal immortality (Brown 1984). In more recent thought, the idea that an infinite
universe implies some form of immortality came to Romantic poet Heinrich Heine
in the first half of the nineteenth century. He wrote: For time is infinite, but the things in
time, the concrete bodies, are finite. They may indeed disperse into the
smallest particles; but these particles, the atoms, have their determinate
number, and the number of the configurations that, all of themselves, are
formed out of them is also determinate. Now, however long a time may pass,
according to the eternal laws governing the combinations of this eternal play
of repetition, all configurations that have previously existed on this earth must
yet meet, attract, repulse, kiss, and corrupt each other again. (Kaufmann 2013,
318) The idea of “cyclic immortality” was
postulated by French socialist Louis Blanqui in his book
Immortality Through the Stars (1872). Friedrich Nietzsche arrived at the same idea,
his famous theory of eternal return
or eternal recurrence, in the 1880s: he recorded in his notes that it first
occurred to him in August 1881, and he published the idea in 1882, in the first
edition of The Gay Science. Subsequently,
it became a central idea in Thus Spoke
Zarathustra (originally published 1883–1891), in which acceptance of the
possibility of eternal recurrence is a defining feature of the Übermensch. However, Nietzsche either did not understand or
ignored the obvious consequence of eternal recurrence, that there will always be
a world, similar to our world until the moment of the observer’s death, but
different in the moment of the death in such a way that the observer will not
die. This implies immortality from the subjective view of any observer. Thus, the
idea of MI (of which QI is an important specific case) is a natural development
of Nietzsche’s idea. Hugh Everett, working on quantum mechanics in the
middle of the twentieth century, was probably the first person to come to the
idea that a constantly branching universe implies immortality from the
subjective point of view, based on his discovery of MWI as an interpretation of
quantum mechanics. However, he never stated this conclusion publicly (Shikhovtsev 2003). It was only at the end of
the twentieth century that the key idea for current purposes – that the existence
of the multiverse implies some form of immortality – became known as “quantum
immortality” following the “quantum suicide” (QS) thought experiment proposed by Moravec (1988), Marchal (1991),
and Squires (1994), and later popularized
by Tegmark (1998). The preservation of information implicit in quantum
mechanics, and known as the “no-hide theorem” (Braunstein
and Pati 2007), is not connected with the idea of QI as it was originally presented by Tegmark
and others. In the original QI theory, human survival happens in only one
of the branches of the quantum multiverse, and preservation of the information
in other branches is not necessary. However, such quantum preservation could be
used by another approach to the resurrection of the dead, i.e. “quantum
archeology,” which is out of the scope of this paper, but has been addressed elsewhere
by the author (Turchin and Chernyakov
2018) and by Jonathan Jones (2017). Previous work has sought to identify the truth or
falsity, and the practical features, of QI, but the idea has only a few vocal
proponents. In the 1990s, Higgo (1998) tried to
present QI as a legitimate theory of immortality, but his analysis is not deep.
About the same time, Robert Charles Wilson explored the possible consequences
of quantum immortality in his short story “Divided by Infinity” (first
published in 1998 in the anthology Starlight
2, edited by Patrick Nielsen Hayden), in which the protagonist survives
multiple suicide attempts (and even a global catastrophe) and is resurrected by
aliens. Allan F. Randall (2004) criticizes QI from the point
of view that its most likely outcome is neither “technological resurrection”
nor “eternal decrepitude,” but chaotic random observers similar to Boltzmann
brains. He does, however, note the usefulness of QI for cryonics. Brett Bevers (2011) explores how QI relates to the Born rule, a central principle in quantum mechanics, and
apparently breaks it. Milan M. Ćirković (2006) correctly mentions
that a theory of personal identity is critical for QI, and proceeds to prove
that, in the case of QI, subjective credence should be
equal to the objective probabilities. Paul Almond (2011) extensively criticizes
the idea that the QS thought experiment could be used as a proof of MWI. Elsewhere
(Almond 2008), he suggests that QS could be a “universal problem solver,” and
that the concept of civilizational-level QS could be used to explain the Fermi
paradox. Greg
Egan’s idea of “dust theory” (see Egan 2009)4
seems to be the next step in developing the idea of QI, similar in significance
to the step from the eternal recurrence in the nineteenth century to the late-twentieth-century
QS thought experiment. In dust theory, something similar to QI happens in every
observer-moment; such moments could exist completely separately from each other,
as random patterns in infinite “dust,” or as Boltzmann brains, but could look
subjectively connected “from inside” based on their similarity. An important
conclusion of such a theory is that there is no need for an external reality other
than the unstructured and endless dust, and that each observer-moment could
have many pasts and many futures. The mathematical theory of
such a world was recently suggested by Marcus P. Müller (2018). The truth
or otherwise of such récherché theories is, however, out
of the scope of this paper; rather, the actual existence of an objective and
structured world, governed by observer-independent laws of physics, is assumed
throughout. Christian
Loew (2017) has suggested an idea similar to Egan’s dust
theory, that of “Boltzmannian immortality,” which is
basically a reincarnation of the eternal return that takes into account Boltzmann brains randomly appearing from vacuum if an empty
universe lasts for an infinitely long period. 2.2 The quantum suicide thought experiment and infinite survival timelinesThe
main idea of the QS thought experiment is that a quantum event, such as radioactive
decay of an atom, will trigger a powerful bomb near me, an observer, with a
probability5 of 0.5. In such a situation, two future timelines are
possible, depending on whether or not the bomb explodes. If MWI is true, both
timelines are real. In one, I continue to exist, and in the other I am instantly
destroyed. Thus, I will observe only the timeline in which the bomb didn’t
explode. This experiment seems similar to the famous thought experiment involving
Schrödinger’s cat, but without the tantalizing idea that the observer could be
in a superposition of dead and alive states. Thus,
QS entails that an observer will always observe a winning result in Russian
roulette, which may seem (to them) as if they have surprising skills of survival.
The main question is whether the inevitable observation of not dying in such an
experiment can be equated to subjective immortality: in MWI, there will always be
a timeline in which the bomb didn’t explode after any number of attempts – but
is this enough to conclude that the observer is immortal? The
QS thought experiment has also been analyzed as a possible proof for MWI: how
many failed attempts at suicide are enough for an observer to conclude that the
MWI is true? Almond and others have invested significant time in proving that no
number of instances of survival in QS could be a proof of MWI. However, as Bostrom notes (2002), if observations are discarded based
on the assumption that in an infinite universe there exists an observer for any
possible observation, science is not possible as observation loses its predictive
power. While
QS requires exotic devices, such as a bomb and a quantum random generator,
there is no reason to think that any ordinary cause of death is different. Dying
will be more complex, but eventually there will be two main types of future
timelines: those in which I died and those in which I survived. However, slower
dying implies some more complex dynamic, such as an increased probability of
survival in an injured state that includes suffering. This will be addressed
later. In
a nutshell, QS entails some form of QI – “quantum immortality” – i.e., for any
observer, there is (at least one) infinite future timeline in which that
observer will continue to exist. However, as will be shown in the next section,
such a result could happen not only in a quantum world, but even in a completely
classical world, if some conditions held relating to the world’s size and the
observer’s internal structure. 2.3 Formalism of multiverse immortalityOne useful instrument when speaking about observers is
the idea of “observer-moments,” that is, the shortest periods of subjective
experience, probably corresponding to one step of the internal human clock (which
has a duration of a few tens of a millisecond). For simplicity’s sake, it is
assumed here that any observer-moment is characterized by the name I and a time-stamp t, and the
observer-moment is thus notated as O(I, t). Then, immortality
can be defined as the following statement: For
any observer-moment O(I, t) there necessarily exists
(at least one) observer-moment O(I, t+1). The following is immediately
implied: There is no last observer-moment
O(I, tlast), so
there is no death. Note
that there is a hidden claim that the existence of O(I, t+1) is sufficient for
immortality. This exact claim typically raises the most objections: while some
might agree that somewhere in the multiverse there exists a copy of me which
survived my death, they claim that such existence is not immortality qua
immortality because of a different identity, or lower “measure,” or some decision-theoretic considerations. Some of these objections will be
discussed in the sections that follow. The
definition of immortality involved here is general and – hypothetically – could
be satisfied through many conceivable processes (e.g. God created the world
this way). What is claimed in MI theory is that the infinitely large size of
the universe is sufficient to satisfy the immortality definition (given a few
other assumptions). 2.5 The logical indefinability of the observer’s deathThere
is a well-known conjecture that is expressed in the following syllogism: “All
humans are mortal (i.e. will die), I am a human, so I am mortal (i.e. I will
die).” Though it is well-known, it has several flaws.
One is the “fallacy of four terms” (Copi and Cohen 1990), as the concept of mortality (and hence of death) has
different meanings in the first premise of the syllogism and in its conclusion.
In the premise, the concept of death is “death-for-others”, i.e. observation of death by outside observers,
or cessation of the living activity of the body. In the conclusion, the concept
of “death-for-me” is used, which means the death
of the observer from the observer’s point of view, typically expressed by
the idea of “nothingness after death” or cessation of the process of
observation. However, by definition, no one can experience and report anything
about nothingness after death, so it is not possible to prove that it will
actually happen. Multiverse
immortality means that death – from the observer’s point of view – is
impossible. In other words, for any state of any observer with time-stamp t0,
there is a possible next state t0+1, and, as everything
possible exists, such an observer exists. Thus, a last moment of experience is
impossible, and death – as the cessation of the process of experiencing – is
impossible. Almond (2011b) attacks this idea and notes that if MWI is not true,
the death of the observer is a consistent explanation of reality, but if it is assumed
that the MWI is true, death in some branches immediately becomes an
inconsistent explanation. According to Almond’s work, this jump between varying
descriptions of death is not logical and undermines the idea of QI. In other
words, if it is agreed that death is theoretically possible, because of a small
world, it should also be agreed that death is possible in the branching world, in
the form of the death of some branches. This is not a question of fact, but one
of interpretation: should the continued existence of a person’s quantum
duplicate (or some other kind of copy) be regarded as immortality or not? The
answer to the problem raised by Almond is connected with the nature of personal
identity, which will be analyzed in the next section. If identity is connected
with the measure of existence, then there is some probability that lowering
this measure is equal to death. If identity depends only on information, then a
change in the number of copies is irrelevant. The nature of death depends on
the nature of personal identity, and death could be described as “the end of
identity.” Another counterargument is that if I am not currently on Mars, that
doesn’t mean that I am dead on Mars. In any given moment, there are a lot of branches which are not happening with me, but it doesn’t
mean that I die every moment – and if the non-existence of a branch is
considered a death, I am dying every second in millions of ways. 2.6 Examples of multiverse immortalityThere
is nothing strange in the idea of MI, when simpler objects and beings are
considered: Numbers are immortal. All numbers appear over and over again in multiple
worlds, and it could be said that any given number is “immortal.” In principle,
the same is true for number series: the number 27 will appear again and again,
but we are not surprised by this, as the number is small compared to the size
of our world, where we can find, for example, 27 ships and 27 sheep. The repetition
of longer numbers in the world becomes more and more surprising – but only
because the world seems to be too small for such repetition. In an infinitely
large and random world, any number or series of numbers will repeat. Simple molecules are immortal. A molecule of water will appear again and again, because
it is very simple, and consists of abundant components. But more complex
compounds are rare. Some short organic molecules are likely to repeat rather
often, while a molecule with around 100 randomly connected atoms will be so
rare that it might appear only once in our Hubble volume. In other words, the
simpler the object, and the more stochastic its environment, the more likely it
will possess something like MI. Biological viruses. Even some living beings could enjoy this type of
immortality in an observable way. Biological viruses of one species are all functionally
equivalent to each other (barring mutation) and the death of one copy is not
the death of the virus. 2.7 Overview of the types of multiverse immortality“Multiverse
immortality” – MI – will be used in what follows as a general term that unites
three subtypes. However, these subtypes may have no observational differences:
eternal return will look like QI if someone’s life history completely repeats
in the future until the moment of death, but, in that moment, becomes different
– and the only difference is that the person will not die. All three types are
identified in Table 1 below and depicted pictorially in Figures 1–3. A useful
metaphor to understand MI is the thought experiment that provides the basis of Jorge
Luis Borges’ short story “The Library of Babel” (originally published in
Spanish, 1941; English translation 1962). In the library of Babel, an infinite
number of copies of all possible books exists. If one
copy of a book disappears, the book still exists within the library, maybe different
in just a few typographical errors. In
passing, it should be noted that a different meaning of the term “quantum
immortality” is sometimes discussed. In this sense, QI is a form of near-death
experience after which a person jumps backward to an earlier point in their
life and relives the moment of a dangerous situation (typically, a car
accident) without dying.6 While some people do have this experience as
a hallucination, it is not the original idea of QI, which cannot be reported to
outside observers, and in which there are no temporal jumps. Quantum
immortality does not require a “quantum mind” or other quantum woo: it is based
solely on MWI, a scientifically respected interpretation of quantum mechanics.
It does not require any quantum effects except the existence of observer copies
in other branches of a multiverse. Table 1. Types of multiverse immortality
Figure 1. Eternal
return with an alternative ending at the moment of death. Figure 2. Big world
immortality. There is another copy of an observer in a causally
disconnected region of the universe, and this observer-copy does not die at the
moment of the observer’s death. Figure 3.
Quantum immortality. There is always a branch of the multiverse in which the
observer does not die. Smaller circles represent “measure decline;” the green line
indicates the timeline of survival. 3. Necessary conditions for multiverse immortality: The huge size
of the universe and a “copy-friendly” theory of personal identity
Two
conditions are essential for MI: that there exists an infinite
number of copies of an observer with alternative life histories, and that the
replacement of an observer with its exact copy is a sufficient condition for immortality. The
first condition is factual: it is a claim that the universe is built in such a way
that, for any situation in which an observer has died, there exists another
copy of the same observer who lived through that exact moment. Note that this
condition is realized by different physical mechanisms for QI and for big world
immortality. In the first case, however, it is realized via branching of the world
wave function, while in the second case, the universe is so large that such
copies will appear in it because of combinatorial effects. While the mechanisms
are different, the result is the same: infinitely many copies ensure the existence
of endless chains of observer-moments.7 The
second condition is not a factual claim, but a decision-theoretic one; it
states that an individual should act as if she is immortal after she learns the
first factual condition (and assuming some type of subject-centered preferences).
Both conditions will be explored in detail in this section. 3.1 Condition 1: Repetition of human minds in the universe3.1.1
Tegmark’s levels of multiverse
Max
Tegmark (Tegmark 2009) identified four levels of the multiverse sufficient
to create a world large enough to include all possible observers’ minds, at
least those the size of a human mind. These are as follows: Level 1. Regions beyond our cosmic horizon,
that is the very large size
of our own bubble. “A generic
prediction of cosmological inflation is an infinite ‘ergodic’
space, which contains Hubble volumes realizing all initial conditions —
including an identical copy of you about 1010^29 m away”
(Tegmark 2009). The scale of chaotic inflation is
supported by observations of anisotropy. One estimate is 10^{10^{10^{122}}}
megaparsecs (Page 2007). Level 2. Other post-inflation bubbles.
Quantum
foam during the Big Bang creates many bubbles with differing laws of physics. Their
existence is supported by ideas that fine-tuning of physical laws is explained
by the observer selection effect, also known as the anthropic principle. Level 3. Many worlds interpretation of
quantum mechanics. Level 4. Mathematical universe: all possible
mathematical structures exist. This is the most simple
explanation of the fact that everything exists at all. The
first level is tentatively supported by data from contemporary cosmology, first
of all, cosmological inflation, as explained by Tegmark.
So, big world immortality in a very large universe receives even stronger
scientific support than QI, which is based on an interpretation of quantum
mechanics that currently remains untestable. However, all this evidence is indirect
and is merely an extrapolation of our best theories of cosmology. Some other
cosmological theories also allow MI, e.g. a cyclic universe, a spatially finite
universe that exists for an infinitely long time via a series of Big Bangs and Big
Crunches (Steinhart and Turok 2002), and a fecund
universe that replicates via black holes (Smolin
1992). The
anthropic principle in a fine-tuned universe can also be regarded as evidence
for a very large universe with a variety of possible physical constants
(Bradley 2009), since numerous “attempts” are required to create the right
combination. By some estimates, as many as 10500 instances might be
required just to arrive at the optimal combination of physical constants.8
There are many cosmological theories, but it is not easy to create a viable
cosmological theory that results in just one small universe that is fine-tuned
for life; in a sense, it is computationally simpler to devise a process that creates
all possible universes. The
more general argument for an infinite universe is philosophical. There is a
process that makes the universe appear from “nothing,” as could be concluded from
the fact of the universe’s existence. For a non-infinite universe, this process
must stop at some point, preventing new universes from appearing. But stopping
this process would require a force acting on
nothingness, i.e. from beyond the universe. However, the universe is, by
definition, the only thing which exists: there can be
nothing beyond it. Thus, the process that created the universe cannot be exhausted.
Approximately the same logic was presented by Kant in his Critique of Pure Reason
(originally published 1781). Among Kant’s celebrated “antinomies,” was that
relating to the finite or infinite extent of the universe in time and space,
where both alternatives were said to be paradoxical. There is, however, a possible
solution: that the universe is neither finite nor infinite, but is instead constantly
growing. One
attractive property of Tegmark’s levels 1 and 2 is
that they are only currently causally
disconnected. They arose from the same causal process of the same Big Bang, and
thus could become connected again at some time vastly distant in the future.
So, copies from levels 1 and 2 have the same ontological status of actual
existence (i.e. actuality, see Section 3.1.4) as any other object in the
observable universe, including even your next-door neighbor. Some
scientists do not subscribe to theories of a multiverse (e.g. Hossenfelder 2018). The
main argument of these critics is that, as other universes are non-observable, they
are beyond real science – but this argument is obviously circular. It is, of
course, difficult to prove that the universe is infinite, but to prove that it
is finite is impossible, so MI cannot be disproved. Interestingly, for MI, it is not necessary that
“everything possible exists” or even that the universe is of infinite size; it
is only necessary that the universe is very large. Another
possible objection to the big world is the idea that only “me-now” actually
exists – similar to the “moving spotlight theory” of now (Deasy
2015), “actual now” (Bitbol 1994), and “ontological
privilege” of now (Frischhut and Skiles 2013)
– and everything unobservable doesn’t exist. But even this will not kill the theory
of multiverse immortality, as in that case,
consciousness becomes an ontological necessity that helps to create the now-moment
and thus can’t be turned off. 3.1.2
The finite size of human minds
Not
only does the universe need to be huge, but human
minds need to be finite in size for multiverse immortality to exist. As the
human brain consists of a finite number of atoms (around 5x1026), it
seems to be finite. Tegmark shows that quantum
effects do not prevent the number of states from being finite, as any quantum
system in the finite space could be in only a finite number of internal states (see Bocchieri and Loinger 1957; Tegmark 2009).
Moreover, the data comprising personal conscious memory has been estimated to
be around 2.5 GB (Carrigan 2006), meaning that only
1010^10 different human minds are possible. Since most human minds will
have immeasurably small differences, the actual number is even smaller. If
one looks at the observer-moment’s size, that is, the current size of an
individual human being’s experience, it is dominated by the visual field, which
may be roughly estimated by the size of the signal that the eye sends to the
brain. It uses one million nerves in the fibers of the optic nerves, each
probably presenting one pixel. By that measure, the actual
size of an observer-moment can be estimated as around 1 MB, and given the
presence of much non-significant peripheral noise, it
is probably even smaller. Thus, there are 101000000 separate
visual observer-moments, most of which are indistinguishable noise. Surely,
the most important part of an observer-moment is not what a person sees, but
what she feels and thinks about it, but these parts are probably less complex and
thus require less storage than the visual field. For example, assuming that the
size of the verbal observer-moment is one sentence, and such a sentence can’t
have more than 20 words, most of which are simple and frequent (and thus selected
from just 1000 of the most common words) it could be concluded that there are
1060 possible sentences, less than the number of particles in the
visual universe. By these measures, the size of the human mind is, indeed,
finite. 3.1.3
Sufficient diversity of the universe
An
infinite universe and a finite size for human minds are not enough to prove MI.
The universe must be diverse enough for any possible mind’s states to appear,
because more than just repetition of events is needed: an escape from even the
worst possible situations is required. Imagine that a spacecraft is falling
into the Sun. At first glance, it seems that there is no chance for the pilot
to survive. However, in a sufficiently diverse universe, an alien spacecraft
could rescue her, or a rogue black hole moving at near-light speed could remove
the Sun – or, most likely, the scenario will turn out to be just a dream. 3.1.4
“Actuality” of the existence of very remote copies
One
important condition is that the whole big universe must actually exist (Menzel 2018). In short, actuality is the idea that some
remote thing exists in the same way that I exist now. In a sense, actuality is “actual
existence,” which implies that there is no “second-rate” form of existence. The
difference becomes clear if one looks at the modal status of events in the
past. Depending on the theory of time adopted, one would say that past events
are either actual (in a timeless universe), or not-actual, i.e. they did exist
but do not exist now, so they are more than just possible events, but less than
currently extant events. There
is an open question in philosophical ontology regarding whether non-causally
connected regions of space can be claimed to actually exist. However, in our
case, in some theories, they are connected, as in MWI and theories of an eternal
universe; or they were connected; or they will be connected. For the validity
of MI, an observer’s remote copies must actually exist, or they should at least
become actual in the future: if they are not actual,
they do not exist. There are three solutions to the actuality problem: 1. Modal realism, that
is, everything possible exists. 2. Actuality is somehow
connected with the “now” moment and is “irradiated” by it. 3. “Relative actuality,”
wherein actuality appears only if two objects are causally connected. In this case,
unobservable regions of the universe are not actual. In
the case of QI, actuality is provided by the fact that the next observer-moment
exists in the future and is causally connected with me-now. But if one starts
to think about copies arising from other Big Bangs, it is easy to ask the
following question. If they are so remote, and so disconnected from our
universe, how could they enable a person’s immortality? This question is an
intuitive expression of doubts regarding the actuality of remote copies.
Intuitively, it seems that the more potential there is for the causal
connection between copies, the better it is for the likelihood that MI is true,
but it is not clear how well-grounded this intuition might be. There is even a
point of view that if all moments of time actually exist, there should be no fear
of death, as each moment will continue to exist (Deng 2015). 3.2 Condition 2: Appropriate theory of personal identity3.2.1
The identity problem In
order for MI to work, a person should treat the continued existence of a copy of
herself as a sufficient condition of her own continued existence. But can she
legitimately make such an assumption? This problem is known as the “identity
problem,” and its main question may be summed up as
“Is information identity of minds enough for personal identity?” Unfortunately, the correct
theory of personal identity remains unknown. Although the issue
initially appears simple, philosophical investigation of personal identity has
notoriously turned out to be difficult, and attempts to describe the problem
and the current approaches will quickly produce controversies and spill
off-topic. In short, the basis of human identity is not known; for a start, the
nature of consciousness and qualia are not known (Chalmers 1996), and thus the
nature of the human mind and of personal identity cannot be determined.
3.2.2
The paradox of “Teleportation to Mars” and
its similarity to multiverse immortality
In
the Mars teleportation paradox (Parfit 1984), a
person is scanned, the resulting information is sent to Mars and the person is recreated
there, and the original is instantly destroyed on Earth. There seems to be no clear
answer to the question of whether or not the original person has survived the
process. This paradox is similar to MI, with just one difference: with MI, no
data are actually sent to a remote celestial body, as the copy is already
there. If a person agrees to Mars teleportation, she also should agree that the
ongoing existence of remote copies, with no prospect of a future time when no
such copies exist, implies some form of immortality. However, there is a caveat
in the case of MI, as the number of surviving copies is constantly declining (as
discussed in Section 5.1) even if it never reaches zero. The
thought experiment devised by Parfit is not a factual
problem – within the thought experiment, all possible facts are known and there
is nothing remaining that could be measured – but a decision-theoretical
problem: a person must make a decision regarding whether or not to use the
teleportation system. This decision depends on the goal system of the person
and the way in which she treats her personal identity. If she must go to Mars, to,
say, save her children, she should use the transportation system. However, if
it is just a recreational trip, the risk of losing something important about one’s
own existence is too high to make it worthwhile. 3.2.3
“Copy-friendly” and “unique-soul” approaches to the problem of the observer
identity
There
are three main views on the nature of personal
identity: 1. Copy-friendly view: Postulates
that informational identity is enough for personal identity, and any exact copy
of me is me. 2. “Privileged original”
point of view: Postulates the existence of some unique substrate of identity that
cannot be measured from outside but which clearly distinguishes the original
from the copies. The typical candidate for this substrate is either a “soul,”
or a causal continuity of the human consciousness between subsequent observer-moments. 3. Open individualism: Denies
the existence of the “identity” at all and postulates that all sentient beings
are the same at their core. Obviously,
if some form of “soul” exists, QI will not work, as death is not real
non-existence. Similarly, open individualism kills the idea of a separate,
unique human, so the existence of any other mind is enough for some form of immortality
to exist. Thus, only two main theories about personal identity are relevant: it
is either information-only or based on causal continuity. Causal
continuity as the nature of human identity is a rather popular view, but it faces
some difficult problems (Wiley and Koene 2016). For
example, if a person experiences narcosis and his brain activity almost stops, should that be regarded as the death of personality?
And what about the abrupt end of a dream? Causal continuity also doesn’t mean
exclusivity of the next state of consciousness, as two new states could follow
smoothly from the “parent” state. If QI is true, this is exactly what happens
within it: minds smoothly branch into two (or more) minds with every new moment
in time. 3.2.4 The merger of observer-identity and memory-identity
Identity
could also be presented as two types of identity: identity as a chain of
memories (which is a copy-friendly view, as any exact copy will have the same
chain of memories), and identity as a chain of connected observer-moments (which
is more dependent on the nature of consciousness). Moreover, the two types of
identity can be separated, as demonstrated in a thought experiment by Parfit (1984), where the memories of one person are transplanted
to another. These two types of identity could result in two types of QI: one as
an amnestic observer, and one involving my memories in some other observer. The
interaction between these two types of immortality is complex, but it may be
assumed that they will eventually merge: the amnestic observer will regain her
memories in some timeline, and thus it eventually will be just one type of
immortality. We,
humans, experience such a merge of observer-identity and memory-identity every
morning when we become awake after bizarre dreams and go through a process of remembering
who we are. The same logic is applicable to the QI situation of very long and
debilitating illness: there are timelines where I will regain full memory of who I am, and, in some sense, I will jump over periods of minimal
or bizarre consciousness. 3.3 Personal identity theories’ connection with various types of multiverse immortalityVarious
combinations of personal identity theories
and big world theories produce various answers about the possibility of MI.
For example, if causal connection of minds is required for identity and MWI is true, then MI is a viable
theory of immortality. Also, MI is a viable theory if only informational
identity is required and only a
cosmological inflation-based big world is true. The
relationships between the particular big-world theories and particular identity
theories are presented in Table 2. This table shows how MI depends on both variables
(both kinds of theories). “Yes” means that MI will work – it is a viable theory
of immortality – while “No” means that it will not work. Both variables are currently
unknown. Simply speaking, MI will not work if the actual world is small or if
personal identity is, in a relevant sense, fragile. Table 2. The relation between immortality, multiverse theories
and personal identity theories
3.4 A rough estimation of the probability that at least some form of MI is trueLooking at Table 2,
it follows that in only two-thirds of the cases do the combination of personal
identity theory and big world theory point to the validity of MI. Certainly,
the numerical estimates are arbitrary, but they indicate that the uncertainty
is very large. It is not easy to put an actual number to subjective credence in
the truth or viability MI. There are serious arguments against any form of MI
based on the “measure decline argument,” but a counterargument will be
presented in Section 5. This all means that a rational subject cannot be sure of either
the truth or falsity of MI. Assume it should be assigned some median credence P
in the theory, e.g. P = 0.5. This is not a zero result, because the consequences
of MI being true or false are asymmetric. For example, a 0.5 chance of winning
1 million USD is not a zero result. As will be shown later, if MI is true, it
implies a very bad outcome by default, which could turn into a very good one
via relatively simple interventions. MI also causes some actions, including suicide,
to have extremely negative utility. 4. Possible
negative effects of multiverse immortality
A naïve view of MI is that it is some surprisingly good thing. However,
there is no free lunch for immortality, and it will be shown in this section that
natural MI could have negative outcomes for humanity. As will be demonstrated
in Section 6, however, MI may be optimized to increase the probability of
positive outcomes. 4.1 The idea of MI is an informational hazard
It
seems that some people are motivated by their ethical positions to object to MI.
The logic is that MI might lead an unstable person to commit suicide,9 so it should
be claimed that QS is false. Quantum-suicide theory can be rejected if MI
itself is false. However, the genie is out of the bottle; thus, it would be more
socially beneficial at this stage to explain that QI has nothing to do with
“suicide” – and that “quantum suicide” was an inappropriate, or even
irresponsible, name, one that might lead an unstable person to think that
suicide will somehow make him or her immortal. If one or another variant of MI is
true, any attempt at suicide will result in failure as well as injury, and will
only increase suffering; this should be explained to compensate for the potential
damage of the original idea of QS. Similarly,
the idea of the existence of the soul might result in a much stronger
temptation toward suicide, as it at least promises another, better world, but I
have never heard that the idea was hidden for fear of resulting in suicide
attempts. Instead, religions try to prevent suicide (even though suicide is
logical by some of their premises) by adding additional rules against it. At
this stage, it appears that MI itself does not promote suicide, and if it is
correctly understood it does not entail that suicide is a good option to stop
suffering. In reality, personal instability may be the main source of suicidal
ideation. If one
really wants to test MI, there is no need to perform an experiment with QS. Anyone
wishing to perform such an experiment would do better to wait until the age of 110.
Moreover, the mere fact that the life on Earth has survived for so long in a dangerous
universe – one full of gamma-ray bursts and large asteroids – for billions of
years may be a case of MI, and perhaps could be interpreted as evidence for the
idea. 4.2 Impossibility of death may be bad
Multiverse
immortality means that death is impossible. It does not mean that any given
person will definitely have a linearly infinite lifespan, as timer resets and
memory loss are possible. But it means that euthanasia is impossible, and one cannot
choose death, no matter how much one might desire it. It follows that there is
no escape from suffering and no way to go to “another” world. If MI is true, euthanasia
seems much more dangerous to a person who already suffers, because it will perpetually
fail and these failures will only increase her suffering. The risk of being
buried alive also becomes great if MI is true, as it is one of the most obvious
forms of strange survival whose objective probability is very small, but which
could present a significant share of all the ways of survival in circumstances
that make it otherwise unlikely. 4.3 Long-term inescapable suffering is possibleIf
death is impossible, someone could be locked into a very bad situation where she
cannot die, but also cannot become healthy again. It is unlikely that such an improbable
state of mind will exist for too long a period – such as a period of millennia
– as, when the probability of survival becomes very small, strange survival scenarios
will dominate (called “low measure marginalization” by Almond (2010), 20–21). One
such scenario might be aliens arriving with a cure for
the illness, but more likely the suffering person will find herself in a
simulation or resurrected by superintelligence in our
world, perhaps following the use of cryonics. István Aranyosi has
summarized the problem as follows,
referring to a previous discussion by David Lewis (2004): “David
Lewis’s point that there is a terrifying corollary to the argument, namely,
that we should expect to live forever in a crippled, more and more damaged
state, that barely sustains life. This is the prospect of eternal quantum
torment” (Aranyosi 2012, 249). If MI is true, and
there is no high-tech escape on the horizon, everyone will experience his own personal
hell. Aranyosi suggests a comforting corollary, based on the idea that the
suffering that is seemingly entailed by MI requires “consciousness, not life as such” (Aranyosi
2012, 252). It follows that I will not experience survival via MI if the damage
to my brain is very high, and so I must find myself in a situation where I did
not endure the damage to my brain that is produced by whatever is the cause of
a person’s death. This means, according to Aranyosi, that being in
the nearest vicinity of death is less probable than being in just “the vicinity
of that vicinity” (2012, 253): the difference is akin to the difference between
constant agony and short-term health improvement. However, it is well known that
very chronic states of health exist that do not affect
consciousness: e.g., cancer, whole-body paralysis, depression, and locked-in
syndrome. I might find myself in a situation where I did not die, or even lose
consciousness (perhaps for some reason that would normally appear a far-fetched
possibility), but I continue to suffer pain or distress. Fortunately, these bad outcomes
become less probable for people living in the twenty-first century, as developments
in medical technology increase the number of possible futures in which any particular
disease can be cured or at least ameliorated, or where a person will be put in cryostasis, or wake up in the next level of a nested
simulation. Aranyosi identifies several other reasons
why eternal suffering is less probable than Lewis conjectured: 1. Early escape from a
bad situation: “According to my line of thought, you should rather expect to
always luckily avoid life-threatening
events in infinitely many such crossing attempts, by not being hit (too hard)
by a car to begin with. That is so because according to my argument the
branching of the world, relevant from the subjective perspective, takes place
earlier than it does according to Lewis. According to him it takes place just
before the moment of death, according to my reasoning it takes place just
before the moment of losing consciousness.” (Aranyosi
2012, 255) 2. Limits of
suffering. “The more damage your brain suffers, the less you are able to
suffer.” (2012, 257) 3. Inability to
remember suffering. “[E]mergence from coma or the
vegetative state is followed by amnesia, and in the minimal conscious state
nothing more in terms of memory than recalling one’s name has been shown to be
present. [...] Hence, what we should expect in the long run [...] is not an
eternal life of suffering, but rather one
extremely brief moment of possibly painful self-awareness – call it the ‘Momentary
Life’ scenario.” (2012, 257–58) 4.4
Bad infinities and bad circles
Multiverse
immortality may cause one to be locked into a very stable but improbable world –
much like the scenario in the Black
Mirror episode entitled “White Christmas” (aired December 16, 2014), in
which a character is locked into a simulation of a room for a subjective 30
million years. Another
bad option is a circular chain of
observer-moments. Multiverse immortality does not require that the “next”
moment will be in the actual future, especially in the timeless universe, where
all moments are equally actual. Thus, there is the
possibility of a “Groundhog Day” scenario (analogous to the plot of the movie Groundhog Day, directed by Harold Ramis, Columbia Pictures, 1993). The circle could be very
short, like several seconds, in which a dying consciousness repeatedly returns to
the same state as several seconds ago, and as it doesn’t have any future
moments it resets to the last similar moment. Surely, this could happen in only
a very narrow state of consciousness, where the internal clock and memory are
damaged. 4.5 Marginalization of measure, strange worlds, and infinite tortureBecause
of the “marginalization of measure” some very improbable and extremely bad worlds
could receive a higher subjective probability. For example, a world in which future
Artificial Intelligence (AI) decided to torture human beings eternally has a
priori low probability, but it could be one of the most probable ways to
survive almost eternally in human form.10 This
is one of the types of s-risks connected with superintelligence
(Sotala and Gloor 2017). In
summary, MI subjectively increases the s-risks connected with AI. 4.6 Dangers of mistakenly ignoring MI and of MI-euphoriaIf MI is true these several extremely bad outcomes could be real possibilities
for any observer. That is why trying to dismiss MI as a weird probabilistic
trick may have an almost infinite negative cost. People who strongly
emotionally believe in MI may choose more risky actions, such as not fastening
seat belts in a car. But the same argument is even more applicable to religious
people who believe in fate. Fatalism is associated with a higher level of
accidents (Şimşekoğlu
et al. 2013), and why the highest world
level is in Iran, a country of particularly devout people. However, the properties
of MI could be used to replace bad outcomes with good outcomes for people who
are currently living. 5. MI as a decision theory
problem
5.1. MI and expected utilityOne
of the main objections to MI is the “measure decline” problem, that is, the
decline of the number of copies of a given person in the multiverse. It may
sound exotic, but can be presented in the form of utility expectations. In a personal
communication, V. Kosoy suggested that the idea of QI
should not affect our choices from the point of view of decision theory if
expected utilities are correctly calculated. Imagine
a thought experiment in which QS is combined
with a lottery. Bob is trying to earn money via a QS experiment (don’t
do it, as most likely you will end up without money and seriously injured or
dead). He asks his friend Alice to buy a lottery ticket, and he takes a sleeping
pill. If the ticket is not a winner, Alice kills Bob while he is asleep. Thus,
Bob will wake up only in the worlds in which he won the lottery (and Alice
didn’t kill him and run away with the winning ticket). However,
the question “Did Bob actually win anything in the game?” depends on how the calculation
of expected utility is performed. For example, if Bob plays a normal lottery
with a probability of 0.1 of winning 1000 USD, then the expected utility of the
game is 100 USD. According to the expected utility objection, this expected
utility doesn’t change regardless of whether the person assumes the truth of
MWI. If Bob doesn’t assume MWI is true, he has a probability of 0.1 of winning
1000 USD, i.e. 100 USD of expected utility. If Bob assumes that MWI is true, Bob
should expect that, of 10 of his copies, 1 will win 1000 USD and 9 will win nothing,
so, given that Bob is randomly
distributed among his copies, Bob again has 100 USD of expected utility. However,
in the case of QS the situation is different, as Bob can’t be distributed
between non-existent copies. In other words, if it is assumed that Bob is
randomly distributed between his actually extant copies at moment t+1, the
QS game becomes a winning game (as only one copy exists); however, looking at the
“worlds” without Bob, the game becomes unattractive. Again, the question
otherwise known as the problem of the validity of QI arises: should a decline in
the number of one’s copies be regarded as death? This
thought experiment could be elaborated depending on the nature of one’s preference
system. For example, imagine a mother needs 1000 USD to pay for a cure for her child.
In this case, it is obvious that if she plays a QS lottery, and wins 1000 USD
in 1/10 of the worlds, she leaves her child without the cure (and a mother) in
9/10 of the worlds, and this is not what she wants. Such values could be called
“world-caring.” Most of our evolutionary evolved values are world-caring,
as evolution favors those who have descendants in the largest share of all
possible worlds. However,
there is another type of values, which doesn’t depend on the number of worlds,
but instead about the existence of at least one world with some property. Consider
a person who cares only about what he might feel. In that case, he could ignore
worlds where he doesn’t feel anything because he doesn’t exist in them. These
two types of preferences, and corresponding solutions of the expected utility
from QS, correspond to the two most accepted decision theories: causal decision
theory (which cares about worlds) and evidential decision theory (which cares
about experiences) (as explored by many, e.g. Soares
and Levinstein 2017). Evidential decision theory
seems to favor QI, as it recommends actions based only on existing experiences,
and in QS a person could only experience not
being killed. However,
both of these theories are imperfect: they do not account for the behavior of
other agents who use the same theory, and, as a result, they recommend that agents
should defect against each other in prisoner’s dilemma-type situations. For
example, even if the QS lottery is a good strategy for
one agent, it would be a complete disaster if everyone constantly employed it
as a strategy because the world would soon be empty (and of course, money would
lose its value). To
compensate for the shortcomings of existing theories, Wei Dai invented Updateless Decision Theory (UDT) (Wei Dai 2009); similar theories have also been put forward by others. The
formulation of UDT is: “UDT specifies that the optimal agent is the one with
the best algorithm – the best mapping from observations to actions – across a
probability distribution of all world-histories” (LessWrong
Wiki 2018; Armstrong 2017). This means that, if such a theory is implemented,
almost all agents will typically win. UDT argues against a QS lottery, since if
everybody plays such a lottery everybody will eventually lose; however, it
argues for cryonics. While
many human goals are oriented to the external world, there is one important
exception. Many people have an extremely negative preference for non-existence,
also known as the fear of death. MI
claims that there is always some form of survival – perhaps not a desirable
form – but survival only in some share of
all worlds, which is called “measure”
because in quantum cases (as well as infinite-world cases) we cannot count
worlds numerically but still need a way to distinguish between more abundant worlds
and less abundant. The measure could
be understood as “amount of existence” or the thickness of the Everett
multiverse branch, but in normal cases, if the “measure” is measured, it will
be just a Born’s rule’s probability. In the
multiverse, there is a difference between having a 1 percent chance of survival
and surviving with a measure of 1 percent, but this
difference typically disappears in the expected utility calculations. The
difference may be equal to the difference between winning 1000 USD with 0.01 probability and having 10 USD. Both events have the same
expected utility, but could have different personal meanings depending on
details of the preferences. If
someone has a preference for existence, MI offers a big utility gain. Moreover,
if everybody were freed of the paralyzing fear of death, it might have a global
positive outcome. But normal MI is bad, as shown in the previous section, so
normal MI, if widely accepted, will have a negative impact on the wellbeing of people
who are currently alive. However, in the case of three alternatives, MI changes
the calculations of expected utility. 5.2 Merging timelines compensate the decline of measureAs
discussed in the previous subsection, one of the main arguments against QI is
that a person’s “measure” (or share of all worlds) declines while branching
continues. However, as the person’s mental state becomes simpler when she is
closer to death, she is de facto merged with “other-she” who also has a
simpler mind now, but who in the past was different from the observer. For
example, imagine a thought experiment where there is an observer Alice1 with
memories (M1, M2… Mn)
and another person, Alice2, with memories (N1, M2…Mn); they have a different first memory. Maybe Alice1’s
first cup was green and Alice2’s was yellow. If, because of the onset of
Alzheimer’s, they both forget the color of their first cup, they are now the
same person with memories (M2…Mn),
which basically means that Alice1’s “measure” doubled! In the case of the complexity
of observer-moments, the result will be the same: the closer to death, the simpler
the person’s observer-moment, and the more people she will merge with. Pereira (2017)
suggested essentially the same argument as counter-evidence of the existence of
very complex minds, calling it the Super-Strong Self-Sampling Assumption. This
simplification of the observer could compensate for the loss of measure because
of MI. In our example, after the measure of Alices doubles, one of them could die, and the
measure will again be reduced to 1. Losing 1 bit of complexity produces a doubling
of the measure, so the simplification process could generate dramatic jumps in measure.
For example, forgetting just 1 kilobit of personal information is equal to a 10300
jump of measure – enough to run the QS experiment with a 0.5 probability of
death 1000 times. If
this logic about an increase in measure is assumed to be true, one could spend an
evening hitting one’s head with a stone and thus losing more and more memories,
and obtaining a higher and higher share of the universe. This is obviously
absurd behavior for a human being, but could be a failure mode for an AI that uses
the utility equation with the measure multiplier to calculate the expected
utility of future states. In other words, an attempt to exclude QI by
multiplying one’s gains in measure changes may pave the way to even more absurd
conclusions. But
this seems to work only in the case of big world immortality, where copies are
not causally connected. Whether the timelines merge in the case of the multiverse
interpretation of quantum mechanics is not clear. One view is that, in quantum
mechanics, a single event may have multiple histories (Feynman, Hibbs, and Styer 2010). In that
case, merging seems to be possible. Almond
(2010) has suggested another argument against QI: that the decline of the
number of observers means the decline of the probability of being one of them.
This works in the same way as in the multiverse Sleeping Beauty thought
experiment (in which Sleeping Beauty wakes 1 or 2 times, depending of the toss
of a coin, either on Monday, or on Monday and Tuesday – the quantum version of
the experiment was described by Peter J. Lewis (2007) and by Sean Carroll
(2014)). She is less likely to be on Tuesday, as there is only one copy of her on
Tuesday, but two copies on Monday. However, in the case of QI, the person
always knows her time position (as t+1 in QI formalism, or Tuesday in the
Sleeping Beauty case) and there is no “dissolving” of the share of observers,
at least until the observer starts to forget her time position because of brain
damage. 5.3. Is MI only a gambler’s fallacy? One
of the main questions raised by researchers of QI is the following: can repeated
survivals in the quantum suicide experiment serve as evidence that MWI is true?
Tegmark (2009) thinks that it is so, but others have suggested
that such survival will be something akin to the “gambler’s fallacy.” That is,
even if a person has survived a few rounds of QS, it is not evidence of any
subsequent survival or of a very large size of the universe. Mallah presents an example of such thinking: Suppose
there are 10 billion people, and 200 of them decide to try QS, so about 100 of
those survive. The effective probability of a person being any one of those QS
survivors is about 100 in 10 billion. This is true in either the single-world
or MWI case, so seeing that you are a QS survivor does not provide evidence
either for or against the MWI. (Mallah 2009–2011, 5) However, this depends on the
total number of people in the world. In Mallah’s example,
it is not surprising (even for an outside viewer) if around 8 rounds (≈ log2200)
of the QS lottery have survivors. However, there is only a 1 in 4096 chance in
the classical world for survivors after 20 rounds, and thus their existence could
be taken as evidence that the actual size of the world is much larger, i.e. it
could serve as evidence for the existence of some form of the multiverse. A
non-violent form of such an experiment would be survival of an observer until
around 140 years old, as for centenarians median life expectancy is around 1
year, and the longest-lived person ever recorded lived only to 122. 6. Possible practical applications of multiverse immortality
6.1 Surviving until life extension technologiesMultiverse
immortality – seen from a subjective perspective – may assist in escaping
death, but not injuries, and thus it can imply an extended period of aging and
dying, with a corresponding increase in suffering. This is the logical
implication in an “ordinary,” low-tech world. Thus, there is nothing a
priori good about MI. But
MI could be useful if interpreted as a probability shift in the direction required
for high-quality extended life, assuming humanity could avoid putting itself at
needless risk by attempting “suicide experiments.” For example, it can be
posited that a sufficiently long aging process will help humans who are alive
now to survive until the appearance of powerful life-extension technologies (de
Grey and Rae 2007). These technologies will produce rejuvenation and might help
us to live indefinitely long lives, even without the help of MI. The additional
survival time needed to reach what de Grey and Rae term “longevity escape
velocity” (in which additions to life expectancy outpace individuals’ aging) may
be just a few decades away, and in some cases this might mean that a person does
not die at the age of 50 years, but instead survives to 90. This is a rather
small shift in life expectancy, which has an a priori probability of a
few percent, and may be not very surprising for the person in question. Trying
to live for as long as possible provides an additional probability shift from MI,
though it also produces benefits even if MI does not exist. Thus, MI should affect
decisions regarding life extension. However,
MI does imply that it is better to choose medical treatments that have only two
possible outcomes – immediate death or complete remission – over treatments
where the process of treatment is slow and painful. For example, if a cancer
patient who believes in MI has to choose between risky surgery, which could end
in either remission or death, or long chemotherapy, for him it is rational to
choose the surgery option, as he will observe only outcomes in which he survives.
If he chose long slow treatment, he could end up in the hell-like eternity of a
very damaged state. 6.2 Multiverse immortality significantly increases the chances of the success of cryonicsMultiverse
immortality significantly increases the chances of cryonics succeeding at life
extension. (“Cryonics” here should be regarded as a placeholder for any radical
life extension or resurrection technology. Note that there is nothing especially
“quantum” in cryonic technology, and that nothing in the following discussion
falls within the category of quantum woo.) If MI is true, the
largest share of timelines where I survive until 2100 include cryopreservation,
as has previously been mentioned by Randall (2004). For example, if cryopreservation’s
success chances are 0.1 percent, and my natural probability of living until the
year 2100 is 1 in a million (excluding the effects of the new life extension
technologies described above), I have 1000 times higher chance to survive to
2100 if I make use of cryonics. As MI entails that some instance of me will
survive to 2100, it is implied that my chances of cryopreservation success grow
to 50 percent (which is our estimation that MI is possible), or 500 times. In
other words, no matter how small the chance of cryonics extending life may be,
MI increases them up to the level of its own probability of success. This
has decision-level consequences: if, initially, you think that cryonics is not worth
trying, then now, after learning about MI, you only have to sign up for cryopreservation,
and MI “will do the rest.” However, if you want to be sure that your friends will
also survive, you will still have to invest in the global quality and
probability of the success of cryotechnologies.
Signing up for cryopreservation replaces the default outcome of the “bad
immortality” of infinitely long aging with a good outcome of resurrection. Signing
up for cryonics is also good from the UDT point of view, as it means that other
people who have similar lines of thought to your own will also sign up. If more
people sign up, cryocompanies will have more money
for research in improving the technology and lowering its price. 6.3 The impossibility of euthanasia and the need for cryothanasiaEuthanasia
assumes that the voluntary death of a terminally ill patient will have two
practical results: cessation of personal suffering, and alleviation of the
burden on the patient’s relatives. The first seems to be the most important reason
for euthanasia, but if MI is true, in her subjective timeline the patient will
experience the failure of the procedure, which most likely means that her suffering
will continue and become even worse.11 Also, her hope of stopping
her suffering will be ruined, and she will witness the shock of her relatives. Even
if our credence in MI is only 0.5, this implies a very high probability of
significantly negative outcomes. However,
if one chooses a combination of euthanasia and cryopreservation, called cryothanasia (Istvan 2014;
Minerva and Sandberg 2017), the most probable line of survival will be regaining
consciousness in the future when a cure for the illness has been developed.
Surprisingly, this is not a popular idea. 6.4 Multiverse immortality increases the chances of the success of digital immortality, and of the acausal trade between the multiverse’s branchesSimilar
logic to that which favors cryopreservation in case of MI is also applicable to
digital immortality, i.e. the idea that humanity will be
reconstructed, based on information traces, by powerful future AI (Bell and
Gray 2000; Turchin 2018b). In the face of MI, digital
immortality becomes one of the most probable outcomes out of all possible ways of
survival. Digital immortality could be an even more likely outcome than
successful use of cryonics, as many people could be reconstructed from their
information traces even if they didn’t sign up for cryonic preservation. The
idea of the resurrection of the dead as a “common task” comes from the Russian
cosmists, and first of all Nikolai Fedorov (see Young
2012), who hoped that all people who lived in the past would be eventually
resurrected – and this surely will happen in some timelines! However,
there is a problem of information loss and resulting non-perfect resurrections.
One possible solution is to replace lost pieces of information with random
information (Almond 2006). In some branches of MWI these random data will be the
same as my data, so an effect similar to MI will be used to reconstruct exactly
me. However, what should be done with the copies that are not exactly similar? In
fact, this is not a big problem, as these not-similar minds will be exact
resurrections of other minds from different universes, and these universes, in
turn, will resurrect me; this could be called cross-resurrection. As a result,
the total measure of all resurrections will be the same and as high as if I
were to be resurrected without the use of random noise.12 6.5 “Universal problem solver” as an example of bad implementation of multiverse immortalityImagine
a bomb, connected to a computer, that will kill me
only if a certain condition is not met. In that case, I will survive in the
worlds in which the condition occurs. This system is an example of a “universal
problem solver”; another specific case is the QS lottery discussed above. This
is a bad application of MI, as the bomb might not work, or might work
ineffectively, leaving me injured but not dead; after a few attempts, such
outcomes will dominate. But the main reason why this is a bad application of MI
is that, if it becomes sufficiently widespread, I (along with everybody else)
will soon find myself in an empty world, where everybody has killed themselves for some reason. Obviously, this would be catastrophic
for my world, far outweighing any personal gain. Almond
(2008) has suggested the possibility of “civilization-level QS,” in which a whole
civilization plays Russian roulette, hoping to win a needed outcome and to escape
the problem of survival of only a part of its members. But such a civilization
would not escape from the curse of low-measure marginalization, as it could end
up in a simulation run by an adverse supercivilization.
This consideration is based on the simulation argument by Bostrom
(2003), which suggests that a significant share of all civilizations are past
simulations run by future supercivilizations, and
that different supercivilizations might have
different goals for running essentially the same simulation (for example, some
of them might be interested in performing non-ethical experiments, and this
could be called “adverse simulation”).13 6.6 Collective survival in a global catastropheThere
are several ways that MI could affect the subjective probability of human
extinction risks: 1. Survival of
closely connected groups of people. There are several hypothetical
situations in which the death of a person has highly reliable causal connections
with the death of a group of people. For example, the collapse of a submerged
submarine will probably kill everybody on board. In such cases, personal
survival will mean that the submarine’s collapse does not happen, and it will appear
that MI enhances the survival of the ship. I have previously explored nuclear
submarines as possible survival refuges in the case of a global catastrophe (Turchin and Green 2017), and this effect could help
increase their survivability. The same is true for a spaceship. If one sits
near the potential target of a nuclear strike, it could lessen the observed
probability of the nuclear war, so this approach could be used as “protection”
against other global risks. 2. Observational
selection effects in probability estimation of the past catastrophes. Some
have suggested that the fact that humanity has survived
without nuclear war may be explained by MI (Kaufman 2013). However, it
is unlikely that World War Three will result in guaranteed human extinction; there will most likely be some survivors, and so this
explanation seems flawed. Others have even suggested that CERN’s collider could
end the world via some disaster stemming from an experiment, and that humanity currently
survives (by luck) only in timelines in which the collider experiences some
technical difficulties (see, for example, the views of Sandberg (2008), who
offers some nice Bayesian calculations, and Yudkowsky
(2008)). 3. Lone wolf
survival. Even if a global catastrophe (such as a pandemic or an asteroid
impact) occurs, MI entails that I could be the only survivor, as I can’t be
killed from my observational point of view, although any other human being can be.
Such an outcome would not technically be human extinction, but it is unlikely that
I would be able to restart the civilization alone. However, I
could be saved by aliens, as in Robert Charles Wilson’s 1998 short story
“Divided by Infinity,” which perfectly illustrates low-measure marginalization. 4. Civilizational
survival. In an entry on his Facebook page (posted December 12, 2018), the
existential risks researcher Phil Torres asked whether it was certain that there
must always be at least one timeline in which the entirety of human
civilization survives all existential risks and ultimately colonizes space to
the extent of its expanding light cone. Assuming that this is an implication of
MI, such timelines will dominate the number of timelines with only one
survivor. This could be regarded as a Plan D for coping with global risks,
after Plan A (prevention), Plan B (survival in refuges (Turchin
2018a)), and Plan C (leaving traces of humanity (Turchin
and Denkenberger 2018)). 6.7 Multiverse immortality in the age of
superintelligence: will I become AI? As
mentioned above, if very advanced and powerful Artificial Intelligence appears
at some point in the future, it may be able to reconstruct me based on my
digital traces. MI increases the subjective probability of observation of the
worlds in which AI will be interested in such reconstruction. I hope that most
AIs that will practice reconstruction for the purpose of digital immortality
will be benevolent and will not cause infinite suffering to the resurrected
people (compare Max Daniel’s (2017) discussion of AI-related risks to humanity).
When
looking at longer timelines, MI implies that the observer will exist for
billions and even trillions of years. The most likely way this could happen is if
the observer ultimately transforms into AI or merges with a future superintelligent (and conscious) AI. If
future AI uses MI to reach some of its goals via a form of QS lottery, it will
disappear from our world, which might be good from the viewpoint of human
beings. If the AI is an unfriendly “paperclip maximizer”
that wants to kill all humans for their atoms (or any other reason), we could
suggest some form of deal (Turchin 2017) in which AI
kills all humanity instantly with 0.99 probability, and completely preserves
us, or even plays the role of benevolent AI, with 0.01 probability. In that
case, the AI receives 0.99 of its expected utility of killing humans (such as
their atoms), but humanity enjoys collective quantum immortality (Almond 2008)
and gains complete survival. As a result, the values of both entities will be
satisfied. Conclusion
In
this article, one of the weird probabilistic arguments connected with our place
in the universe, i.e. so-called quantum (or multiverse) immortality,
was explored. Multiverse immortality has some probability of being true; though
its truth is not certain, its probability is large enough for us to be wary of
its bad consequences, or at least to use it as a possible multiplier to boost
the chances of success of some already-existing processes, such as cryonic
preservation and storage. The effects of MI on different important practices
such as cryonics and euthanasia are summed up in Table 3. Given
the significant uncertainty regarding the truth of MI – and the fact that, even
if MI is true, it is more likely than not to contribute to bad outcomes – it can
be regarded only as a Plan D for achieving personal immortality. In this
scenario, Plan A is life extension until the
development of beneficial Artificial Intelligence capable of fighting aging, Plan
B employs cryonics, and Plan C is digital immortality (Turchin
2015). From a practical point of view, MI is best viewed as an additive that
increases the chances of success of other life extension technologies. Table 3. The outcome matrix for multiverse
immortality and significant life choices
Notes 1.
However, some do find QI and related theories of immortality plausible (e.g. Loew 2017). 2.
Thus, “s” stands for “suffering.” 3.
Use of terms: “multiverse immortality” is the technically correct term.
It is an umbrella term for two separate subtypes: “big world immortality” and “quantum
immortality.” But as quantum immortality is the most accepted term, it is used
throughout this paper wherever the difference between MI and QI is not material
to the discussion. 4.
The dust theory is best known from Greg Egan’s short story “Dust” (first
published in 1992) and his 1994 novel Permutation
City. 5. A good popular introduction can be found in an io9 article on quantum suicide, written
by Alasdair Wilkins (2012). 6.
For examples, see a Reddit discussion (Reddit c.2018), initiated by the user “rainboughost.”
Participants offer numerous recollections of experiences that might potentially
have been fatal. 7. Note that here “endless” does
not mean “infinite,” as circular timelines are possible and actual infinity is
impossible. 8. This topic is obviously
controversial. For more discussion, see Friederich
2018. 9.
As it seems has already happened with Everett’s
daughter, Elizabeth, judging by a suicide note in which she expressed the hope –
obviously impossible from the viewpoint of QI thinking – to “end up in the
correct parallel universe to meet up w[ith] Daddy” (Byrne 2010, 352). 10. As in Harlan Ellison’s classic science fiction story
“I Have No Mouth, and I Must Scream” (first published 1967, in the March issue
of If: Worlds of Science Fiction). 11. This assumes he will have the traumatic experience
of something akin to regaining consciousness in a morgue, and will feel pain
again without the amelioration of painkillers, plus enduring whatever damage might
have resulted from the method used in the euthanasia attempt. 12. Elsewhere (Turchin 2018c),
I discuss this resurrection approach in more detail. 13.
It is unlikely that civilization-level QS provides a solution for the Fermi
paradox, because it is unlikely that all
civilizations will choose this path, as it is clearly very risky; thus, it
fails the “non-exclusivity” principle for any valid Fermi paradox solution (Brin 1983). References Almond, P. 2006. Many-worlds assisted mind uploading:
A thought experiment. Almond P. 2008. Civilization-level quantum suicide. Almond P. 2010. Repeated quantum suicide would not suggest that MWI is correct – even to the person doing it. Almond P. 2011a. Quantum suicide and inconsistency: Assuming you will survive
quantum suicide may be simplistic. Almond P. 2011b. Repeated quantum suicide would not suggest that MWI is correct: A stronger version of the argument. Aranyosi, István. 2012. Should we fear
quantum torment? Ratio 25(3): 249–59. Armstrong, Stuart. 2017. Anthropic decision theory for
self-locating beliefs. Future of Humanity Institute technical
report. Bell, Gordon, and Jim Gray. 2000. Digital immortality.
Communications of the
ACM 44(3): 28–31. Bergström, Lars. 2012. Death and eternal recurrence. In The
Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death, ed. Ben Bradley, Fred Feldman, and
Jens Johannson, 167–85. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press. Bevers, Brett M. 2011. Can many-worlds survive a quantum doomsday? Bitbol, Michel. 1994. IS NOW
A MOMENT IN TIME? A discussion of McTaggart’s
argument against the reality of time from a transcendental idealist standpoint.
(Orig. pub. as “Now and time.”) Bocchieri, P., and A. Loinger. 1957.
Quantum recurrence theorem. Physical Review 107: 337. Bostrom, N. 1999. The Doomsday argument is alive and kicking. Mind
108: 539–50. Bostrom, N. 2002. Self-locating belief in big worlds: Cosmology’s missing
link to observation. Journal of Philosophy 99: 607–23. Bostrom, N. 2003. Are we living in a computer simulation? Philosophical Quarterly 53: 243–55. Bradley, Darren. 2009. Multiple universes and observation
selection effects. American Philosophical Quarterly
46: 61–72. Braunstein, Samuel L., and Arun K. Pati. 2007. Quantum information cannot be completely hidden
in correlations: Implications for the black-hole information paradox. Physical Review Letters 98: 080502-1–082502-4. Brin, Glen David. 1983. The “great silence”: The controversy
concerning extraterrestrial intelligent life. Quarterly
Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society 24: 283–309. Brown, Geoffrey. 1984. The cosmological theory of Empedocles. Apeiron 18: 97–101. Byrne, Peter. 2010. The many worlds of Hugh Everett
III: Multiple universes, mutual assured destruction, and the meltdown of a nuclear
family. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Carrigan Jr., Richard A. 2006. Do potential SETI signals need
to be decontaminated? Acta Astronautica 58: 112–17. Carroll, Sean. 2014. Quantum Sleeping Beauty and the
multiverse. July 28. Chalmers, David J. 1996. The conscious mind: In search
of a fundamental theory. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Ćirković, Milan M. 2006. Is quantum suicide painless? On an apparent violation
of the principal principle. Foundations of Science 11: 287–96. Copi, Irving, and M. Cohen. 1990. Introduction to logic.
New York: Macmillan. Daniel, Max. 2017. S-risks: Why they are the worst existential
risks, and how to prevent them. Foundational Research Institute. de Grey, Aubrey, and Michael Rae. 2007. Ending aging:
The rejuvenation breakthroughs that could reverse human aging in our lifetime.
New York: St. Martin’s Press. Deasy, Daniel. 2015. The moving spotlight theory. Philosophical Studies 172: 2073–2089. Deng, Natalja. 2015. On whether
B-theoretic atheists should fear death. Philosophia 43: 1011–1021. Egan, Greg. 2009. Dust Theory FAQ. Eliade, Mircea. 2005. The myth of the eternal return. Trans.
Willard R. Trask. 2nd paperback ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
(Orig. pub. 1949.) Feynman, Richard P., Albert R. Hibbs,
and Daniel F. Styer. 2010. Quantum mechanics and path
integrals. Emended ed. New York: McGraw-Hill. Friederich, Simon. 2018. Fine-tuning.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018
ed.). Frischhut, Akiko M., and Alexander Skiles.
2013. Time, modality, and the unbearable lightness of being. Thought: A
Journal of Philosophy 2: 264–73. Higgo, James. 1998. Does the “many-worlds” interpretation
of quantum mechanics imply immortality? Hossenfelder, Sabine. 2018. Scientific theory
and the multiverse madness. National Public Radio. Istvan, Zoltan. 2014. Should cryonics,
cryothanasia, and transhumanism
be part of the euthanasia debate? Huffington Post. June 23 (updated
August 21). Jones, Jonathan A. 2017. Technological resurrection:
A thought experiment. [No publication details provided.] Kaufman, Jeff. 2013. Is our continued existence evidence
that mutually assured destruction worked? LessWrong.
June 19. Kaufmann, Walter A. 2013. Nietzsche: Philosopher, psychologist,
antichrist. Princeton, NJ, and Oxford: Princeton University Press. (Orig.
pub. 1950.) LessWrong Wiki. 2018. Updateless decision
theory. Lewis, David. 2004. How many lives has Schrödinger’s cat?
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82: 3–22. Lewis, Peter J. 2007. Quantum
Sleeping Beauty. Analysis
67: 59–65. Loew, Christian. 2017. Boltzmannian
immortality. Erkenntnis 82: 761–76. Mallah, Jacques. 2009–2011. Many-worlds interpretations can not imply “quantum immortality.” arXiv:0902.0187
[quant-ph]. Marchal, Bruno. 1991. Mechanism and personal identity. In Proceedings of WOCFAI, 91: 335–45. Menzel, Christopher. 2018. Actualism.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 ed.). Minerva, Francesca, and Anders Sandberg. 2017.
Euthanasia and cryothanasia. Bioethics
31: 526–33. Moravec, Hans. 1988. Mind children: The future of robot
and human intelligence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Mülle, Markus P. 2018. Law without law: From observer states
to physics via algorithmic information theory. arXiv:1712.01826v2 [quant-ph]. Page, Don N. 2007. Susskind’s challenge
to the Hartle-Hawking no-boundary proposal and possible
resolutions. Journal of Cosmology and Astroparticle
Physics 01(January)004: 1–20. Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford and
New York: Oxford University Press. Pereira, Toby. 2017. An anthropic argument against the
future existence of superintelligent artificial intelligence. arXiv:1705.03078v1 [cs.AI]. Randall, Allan F. 2004. Quantum miracles and immortality.
Quantum 5(8). Reddit. c.2018. Quantum immortality.
Is the glitch the fact that some people remember being reset? (Discussion of
quantum immortality initiated by user “rainboughost.”) Sandberg, Anders. 2008. Bayes, Moravec
and the LHC: Quantum suicide, subjective probability and conspiracies. Andart blog. September 22. Shikhovtsev, Eugene B. 2003. Biographical sketch
of Hugh Everett, III. Şimşekoğlu, Özlem, Trond
Nordfjærn, Mohsen Fallah Zavareh, Amin Mohamadi Hezaveh, Amir Reza Mamdoohi, and Torbjørn Rundmo. 2013. Risk perceptions,
fatalism and driver behaviors in Turkey and Iran. Safety Science
59(November): 187–92. Smolin, Lee. 1992. Did the universe evolve? Classical and Quantum Gravity 9: 173–91. Soares, Nate, and Benjamin A. Levinstein.
2017. Cheating death in Damascus. Technical report. Machine Intelligence
Research Institute. Sotala, Kaj, and Lukas Gloor. 2017. Superintelligence as
a cause or cure for risks of astronomical suffering. Informatica 41: 389–40. Squires, Euan
J. 1994. The mystery
of the quantum world. 2nd ed. New York and
Oxford: Taylor & Francis. Steinhardt, Paul J., and Neil Turok.
2002. Cosmic evolution in a cyclic universe. Physical
Review D 65: 126003-1–126003-20. Tegmark, M. 1998. The interpretation of quantum mechanics: Many worlds
or many words? Fortschritte Der Physik 46: 855–62. Tegmark, M. 2009. The multiverse hierarchy. arXiv:0905.1283 [physics.pop-ph]. Turchin, Alexey. 2015. Immortality roadmap. LessWrong.
July 29. Turchin, Alexey. 2017. Messaging future AI. Manuscript. Turchin, Alexey. 2018a. Approaches to the prevention of global
catastrophic risks. The Human Prospect 7(2): 52–66. Turchin, Alexey. 2018b. Digital immortality: Theory and protocol
for indirect mind uploading. Manuscript available at PhilPapers. https://philpapers.org/rec/TURDIT
(accessed December 22, 2018). Turchin, Alexey. 2018c. Resurrection of the
dead via multiverse-wide acausual cooperation.
LessWrong.
September 3. Turchin, Alexey, and Maxim Chernyakov.
2018. Classification of approaches to technological resurrection. Manuscript available at PhilPapers. Turchin, Alexey, and David Denkenberger.
2018. Surviving global risks through the preservation of humanity’s data on the
Moon. Acta Astronautica 146: 161–70. Turchin, Alexey, and Brian Patrick Green. 2017. Aquatic refuges
for surviving a global catastrophe. Futures 89: 26–37. Wei Dai (2009). Towards a new decision theory.
LessWrong. August 13. Wiley, K.B., and R.A. Koene.
2016. The fallacy of favoring gradual replacement mind uploading over scan-and-copy.
Journal of
Consciousness Studies 23: 212–35. Wilkins, Alasdair. 2012. Quantum suicide: How to prove
the multiverse exists, in the most violent way possible. Io9. March 8. Young, George M. 2012. The Russian cosmists: The esoteric futurism of
Nikolai Fedorov and his followers. Oxford and New
York: Oxford University Press. Yudkowsky, Eliezer. 2008. How many
LHC failures is too many? LessWrong. September 21. |