Genetic Engineering and
the Consent of Future Persons Martin Gunderson Department of Philosophy Macalester College Journal of Evolution and Technology - Vol. 18 Issue 1 – May 2008 – pgs 86-93 http://jetpress.org/v18/gunderson2.htm Abstract
The debate over whether
germ-line genetic engineering is justified on the basis of the consent or
presumed consent of future generations is mired in philosophical
confusion. Because of this, the
principle of informed consent fails to provide a reason to restrict germ-line
genetic engineering. Most recent bioethicists ground the consent requirement on
individual autonomy. While conceptually coherent, the notion of individual
autonomy also fails to provide a reason for prohibiting germ-line genetic
engineering. Moreover, it offers little in the way of useful guidance for
regulating genetic engineering. I argue, however, that respect for autonomy in
the sense of moral agency – the ability to reflect on
moral considerations and conform one’s behavior to those reflections – provides a principle that can be used for a nuanced
evaluation of proposals for genetic engineering. Introduction The doctrine of informed
consent is central to medical ethics. It is now a widely accepted legal and
moral principle that competent adults are not to be subjected to medical
treatment without their consent (Faden and Beauchamp 1986, chapters 4-6;
Appelbaum et al. 1987, chapter 2). In addition, genuine consent requires
knowledge of relevant facts (Faden and Beauchamp, 248-55). This standard is even embedded in human
rights documents.[1] Some have
thought that this poses a problem for germ-line genetic engineering because
future generations will not have consented to being genetically engineered
(Billings et al. 1999, 1873-75; Fletcher 1983, 542-43; Habermas 2003, 85-86;
Harding 1991, 486-87; Lappé 1991; Marks 2002, 122-23). I argue that it is a
conceptual confusion to talk of future persons consenting to present
practices. As a result, it is a
confusion to reject germ-line engineering because it will affect persons in the
future who have not consented. I also argue that the notions of hypothetical
consent, proxy consent and presumed consent cannot be spelled out with
sufficient precision to justify regulation of germ-line genetic engineering. In
general, the doctrine of informed consent is not helpful in offering guidance
for regulating germ-line genetic engineering. Instead we should consider the
value of moral autonomy, which turns out to provide a nuanced way of evaluating
various proposals for genetic engineering. It does not, however, provide
justification for a blanket prohibition of germ-line genetic engineering, even
when it is for purposes of enhancement. Current and Subsequent Consent Speaking of the lack of
consent of future persons is ambiguous. It might mean that they do not consent
at the present time because they do not exist –
lack of current consent. It might also mean that they will not consent when
they do come to exist – lack of subsequent consent.
Both of these produce absurdity. Consider first lack of current consent. Talk
of the present consent of future persons involves a conceptual confusion
because it is incoherent to speak of a person who is not yet born as currently
consenting to an action at the present time. Hence, it is also conceptually
incoherent to speak of a future person as currently failing to consent to an
action. It follows that it is also absurd to speak of this failure as providing
a reason for prohibiting a present action. It is tempting to think that
what really matters is lack of subsequent consent, not lack of present consent.
Work on paternalism several decades ago explored the issue of subsequent
consent for past actions, and the insights generated are also useful in the
present context. While philosophers such as Rosemary Carter and Gerald Dworkin
relied on subsequent consent to justify prior paternalism, Joel Feinberg,
Tziporah Kasachkoff and John Kleinig produced compelling arguments for not
relying on subsequent consent (Carter 1977; Dworkin 1972; Feinberg 1986;
182-183, Kasachkoff 1994; Kleinig 1984). On their arguments, consent plays a
moral role that cannot be fulfilled by subsequent consent. They correctly argue
that consent functions as way of allowing another to do what would otherwise be
morally or legally impermissible. Consent functions to facilitate, or at least
not prevent, an action (Kasachkoff 1994, 17; Kleinig 1984, 98). Consent is closely connected
to rights. As Heidi Hurd argues, consent can create rights as well as turn what
would otherwise be a wrongful act into an act that is right. It can, for
example, give another person a right to do something that would otherwise be
wrong (Hurd 1996, 123-124). In addition, consent is built into the structure of
various rights to provide one way of waiving or of not standing on a right
(Alexander 1996, 165-166). This is true in the case of the right being dealt
with here – the right not to be medically treated
without one’s consent. In this case, consent is so integral to the structure of
the right that the right is partially defined in terms of consent. There is no
right, per se, not to receive medical treatment. It is not wrong, for example,
to treat a child or a person with a severe mental disability who is not able to
consent. Rights that have consent built
into their structure have two important functions. They protect the
right-holder in a particular area from incursions by making such incursions
morally wrong or illegal. They also protect the right-holder from the claims
based on considerations of general welfare (Dworkin 1977, xi). Second, consent
allows the right-holder to control these normative protections and hence to
shape the behavior of others. Hence these rights also provide for the
right-holder’s autonomy as well as protecting the right-holder from harm. (The
assumption, of course, is that those tempted to violate rights will be
motivated by such normative considerations.) In order for consent to play
these vital moral and legal roles the consent must be given prior to the
activity that would otherwise constitute a violation of rights or other
impermissible act. Stealing my property, to use Kasachkoff’s example, remains
an act of theft, even if I later approve of the act. I cannot convert what was a theft into an act of borrowing (Kasachkoff
1994, 15). If the consent incorporated into the notion of a right such as the
right not to be medically treated without consent could be subsequent, then
rights could not play the role they do. Right-holders who claim their rights in
order to protect themselves from incursion would be offered scant protection if
we had to wait to see whether consent is forthcoming in the future. Rights that
serve to protect the right-holder against claims based on welfare
considerations, for example, would be weak protection indeed if we could not be
sure whether the right would be waived by future consent. “Subsequent consent”
does not function as consent at all. What seems to be consent after the fact is
in fact, as previously noted, something more like forgiveness or approval
(Feinberg 1986, 182-183; Kasachkoff 1994, 18; VandDeVeer 1986, 67-69).[2] In the end, it is a conceptual
confusion to speak of future persons as consenting to present practices. If
this does not make sense, then it will not do to base justifications and
conclusions on this concept. This includes the view that germ-line genetic
engineering is unjustified because the consent of future generations is not
secured. Even if it made sense to talk
about the subsequent consent of future persons, lack of consent would not
provide a justification for a blanket prohibition on germ-line genetic
engineering. In fact, it provides
little useful guidance. We are typically in no position to make reasonable
predictions about what people in future generations will approve of and hence
what they will consent to. The problem is that the cultural context may change
over a number of generations. In addition, we are not able to predict what
technologies will be available in the future and how they will shape values.
Finally, we do not know how the moral and political debates that influence
policy will turn out. Jürgen Habermas is correct that even such goods as
enhanced intelligence and memory may not be desired by some people (Habermas
2003, 85-86). As Habermas notes, memory, for example, can become a curse for
people who have things they need to forget (Habermas 2003, 85; Reiss 1999, 85). Søren Holm gives additional
reasons for rejecting the argument that germ-line genetic engineering is
morally problematic because the future generations affected did not consent
(Holm 2002, 88). Holm notes, for instance, that it is quite usual to make
decisions that have far reaching effects on one’s descendants (e.g., deciding
what country to live in). If these decisions are not problematic, why should we
regard germ-line engineering as a problem? Holm also points out that lack of
consent would have to be equally problematic even if future generations were
benefited (Holm 2002, 88). It would be absurd, however, to refuse to engage in
germ-line genetic engineering to prevent a person from being born with a
devastating genetic disease such as Tay Sachs on the grounds that the future
persons would not have consented. It might be thought that all
of this is simply another way of making the case for those who claim that
germ-line engineering is unjustifiable. Whether such talk of informed consent
is conceptually incoherent or practically impossible, it might be argued, there
is no consent and hence no justification. This reply does not succeed, however.
As previously noted, we cannot understand the notion of the right protected by
the consent requirement wholly independently of consent. Hence, the right not
to be subjected to medical treatment without consent applies to those who are in
some sense able to consent. If it does not make sense to speak of future
generations consenting to a particular present treatment (e.g., germ-line
genetic engineering), then it does not make sense to say that they have a right
not to be treated without their consent. Hypothetical Consent, Proxy Consent and
Presumed Consent If it is a confusion to speak
of the consent of future persons, it might instead be argued that talk about
future consent is really just a shorthand way of talking about hypothetical consent,
proxy consent, or presumed consent. I begin with a consideration of
hypothetical consent. On this view, germ-line engineering is wrong if the
person who will be affected by it would
not have consented to it. Unlike subsequent consent, there are cases in which
it is not a conceptual confusion to speak of hypothetical consent (what a
person would consent to). This is most clear when we know the values of a
formerly competent patient who is not rendered incompetent. In some cases we
can also make a reasonable prediction based on the current cultural context.
For example, in most cases, though certainly not all, a person who is brought
unconscious into an emergency ward would want to receive life-saving medical
treatment. This will not work in the case of future persons, however. The
problem is that the persons are in the future. We are not now in a position to
speak coherently of what future reasonable persons would consent to at the present time when decisions
regarding germ-line engineering are being made. It might be replied that we can
speak of what they would consent to in
the future, but this simply loops us back to the issue of subsequent
consent, and it is clear from the previous section that that gets us nowhere. The major problems with hypothetical
consent also arise if we attempt to use proxy consent as a reason for
regulating germ-line genetic engineering. If we cannot know what a person would
consent to, we are not in a position to substitute consent for that person. As
Beauchamp and Childress note, substituted judgment (proxy consent) only works
for previously competent persons in cases in which the person deciding knows
what the person would have wanted (Beauchamp and Childress 2001, 100). It does
not work for never competent persons and certainly not for persons who will not
be born until some time in the distant future. What we can do, however, is to
act in what we believe to be the person’s best interest. In this case, the
consent of the person being treated drops out of the picture and is replaced by
a best interest standard. But, can’t we at least presume
consent in the case of primary goods – goods such as intelligence
that are reasonable to value whatever else one values? Fritz Allhoff, for
instance, argues that we can presume the consent of future persons to germ-line
engineering that enhances primary goods (Allhoff 2005, 50). The problem is that
for any particular primary good we can always imagine a person who has a set of
values such that he or she would reject the primary good. Some might even
reject enhanced intelligence on the ground that it creates envy in others or
makes it more difficult to pursue other character important character traits,
as Habermas has noted (Habermas 2003, 85-86). In order to develop an argument
for permitting germ-line genetic engineering in such cases, we need to argue
that persons, as moral agents, are committed to certain values that can be
enhanced. It will not do simply to talk about what they would or might or could
be presumed to consent to based on their actual future values. In light of the confusions
generated by speaking of consent and hypothetical consent, it would be better
simply to directly consider reasons for germ-line genetic engineering.
Considering the reasons that justify the doctrine of informed consent in the
first place is a good way to begin, since it promises to capture the intuitions
that lead to talk of consent while avoiding the confusions implicit in applying
the notion of consent to future generations. Autonomy
Most who write about the
doctrine of informed consent claim that consent is important because it
protects autonomy (Beauchamp and Childress 2001, 77; Hurd 2002, 124). Bioethicists often spell out autonomy in
terms of self-governance according to which one is autonomous when one is able
to act in accord with one’s personal or authentic values (Beauchamp and
Childress 2001, Chapter 3). This includes both being free from certain sorts of
duress or coercion and having adequate information. Different analyses of autonomy
specify in various ways what counts as duress and adequate information. I shall
refer to this sort of autonomy as “individual autonomy” in order to distinguish
it from moral autonomy (the ability to act as a moral agent). We cannot rely on
individual autonomy to provide reasons for regulating germ-line genetic
engineering. Individual autonomy is characterized in terms of individual
desires and values; and, as previously noted, we are not now in a position to
know what desires and values persons in future generations will have. This is
true even in the case of primary goods. As Søren Holm notes, it is not clear
why we should refrain from germ-line engineering if we cannot foresee a
definite harm to future generations (Holm 2002, 88). This is certainly true in
the case of specific desires that future persons might have. A better bet is to seek
guidance by relying on moral autonomy. Moral autonomy consists of the ability
to reason and act in accord with the requirements of morality. Those who have
this capacity are moral agents. Moral agents have the ability to formulate and
reflect on moral principles, to notice the morally relevant features of various
situations, to provide moral justifications for a range of actions, and to
respond with appropriate moral feelings such as sympathy and compassion. Immanuel Kant provided the
classical statement of morally autonomy. For Kant, a person acts autonomously
when the person acts on the basis of reasons that could be adopted by everyone
without inconsistency. Kant stated this rather formally in terms of the first
formulation of the categorical imperative –
“Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time
will that it become a universal law” (Kant [1785] 1996, 73). For Kant, merely
acting on the basis of authentic desires is not enough to achieve autonomy.
Note that my characterization of moral autonomy is considerably broader than
Kant’s. In particular, the notion of moral autonomy offered here does not
require acceptance of Kant’s view of the categorical imperative. On the basis of respect for
moral autonomy, we have reason to engage in genetic engineering (germ-line or
somatic) to the extent to which it could enhance moral agency – the ability to perceive the morally relevant features of
situations, have the requisite moral emotions, formulate moral justifications
and act in light of them. Those who are committed to being moral agents also
have reasons to seek enhancement of these qualities insofar as they can improve
moral agency. We also have reason to refrain from genetic engineering to the
extent to which it undermines moral agency. Genetic engineering that enhances
the ability of a person to suppress violent urges when reason dictates clearly
enhances moral agency, while genetic engineering that deadens his or her
empathy detracts from moral agency. What is central is our respect
for the value of moral agency itself, not our respect for the particular
choices of individuals who do not yet exist. Respect for moral autonomy provides
a nuanced way of thinking about germ-line genetic engineering. It does not,
however, provide reason for simply prohibiting such engineering, even if
genetic engineering is used for purposes of enhancement. Ronald Munson and Lawrence
Davis also note that autonomy is the crucial value protected by consent, but
they argue for a much stronger conclusion. They argue that since potential progeny do not exist they have no autonomy
that could be tampered with and hence “…nothing to protect by their requiring
‘informed consent’” (Munson and Davis 1992, 143). As a result, there is
no work for consent to do in protecting their autonomy. Munson and Davis are
right that consent is a non-issue. The reason that consent is a non-issue,
however, is because it fails to function to permit what would otherwise be a
violation of autonomy, not because it is impossible to thwart the autonomy of
non-existing persons. In particular, there are worries about moral
autonomy. Respect for moral autonomy
and hence moral agency, as opposed to respect for the choices of particular
agents, requires us to act so that the people who come after us will be able to
act as morally autonomous beings, whatever their values and desires. Conclusion What lies behind the argument
that germ-line engineering should be prohibited because of a lack of consent is
a concern for autonomy. There are, however, different ways of looking at
autonomy, and it is moral autonomy rather than individual autonomy that is
relevant for considerations of germ-line genetic engineering. Moral autonomy
does not, by itself, provide a reason for a blanket prohibition of germ-line
genetic engineering whether for purposes of therapy or enhancement. It does,
however, provide a principle for evaluating particular proposals for germ-line
genetic engineering.[3] References
Alexander, L.
1996. The moral magic of consent (II). Legal
Theory 2(3): 165-174. Allhoff, F. 2005. Germ-line genetic enhancement and Rawlsian primary goods. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal. 15(1): 39-56. Appelbaum, P. S., C. W. Lidz, and A.
Meisel. 1987. Informed consent: legal
theory and clinical practice. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Beauchamp, T. L. and J. F. Childress,
2001. Principles of Biomedical Ethics,
5th ed. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Billings, P. R., R. Hubbard, and S. A.
Newman. 1999. Human germline gene modification: A dissent. The Lancet 353(9167): 1873-1875. Carter. R. 1977. Justifying paternalism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7(1):
133-145. Council
of Europe. 1997. Convention for the
protection of human rights and dignity of the human being with regard to the
application of biology and medicine: Convention on human rights and biomedicine. Retrieved July 26, 2006, from http://conventions.coe.int/treaty/en/treaties/html/164.htm
Davis, J. K. 2004. Precedent autonomy and
subsequent consent. Ethical Theory and
Moral Practice 7(3): 267-291. Dworkin, G.
Paternalism. 1972. The Monist 56(1):
64-84. Dworkin, R.
1977. Taking rights seriously.
Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Faden, R. R. and T. L. Beauchamp. 1986. A history and theory of informed consent.
New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Feinberg, J.
1986. Harm to self. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. Fletcher, J. C. 1983. Moral problems and
ethical issues in prospective human gene therapy. Virginia Law Review 69(3): 515-546. Habermas, J. 2003. The future of human nature, tr. W. Rehg, M. Pensky, and H. Beister. Cambridge: Polity Press. Harding, J. 1991. Beyond abortion: Human
genetics and the new eugenics. Pepperdine
Law Review 18(3): 471-512. Holm, S. 2002. The role of informed
consent in genetic experimentation. In A
companion to genethics, ed J. Burley and J. Harris. Malden, MA, Oxford, and
Victoria Australia: Blackwell Publishing: 82-91. Hurd, H. 1996. The moral magic of consent. Legal Theory. 2(2): 121-146. Kant, I.
[1785] 1996. Groundwork of the
metaphysics of morals. In Practical
philosophy, ed. and tr. M. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kasachkoff, T. 1994. Paternalism: Does
gratitude make it okay? Social Theory and
Practice. 20(1): 1-23. Kleinig, J.
1984. Paternalism. Totowa, NJ: Rowman
and Allanheld. Lappé, M. 1991. Ethical issues in
manipulating the human germ line. Journal
of Medicine and Philosophy. 16(6):
621-639. Marks, S. P. 2002. Tying Prometheus down:
The international law of human genetic manipulation. Chicago Journal of International Law 3(1): 115-136. Munson, R. and L. H. Davis. 1992.
Germ-line gene therapy and medical imperative. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 2: 137-158. Reiss, M. J. 1999. What sort of people do
we want? The ethics of changing people through genetic engineering. Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public
Policy. 13(1): 63-92. UNESCO (General Conference of the United
Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization). 1997. Universal declaration on the human genome
and human rights. Retrieved July
26, 2006, from http://www.ohchr.org/english/law/genome.htm VanDeVeer, D. 1986. Paternalistic intervention: The moral bounds of benevolence. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Notes [1] Chapter II,
Article 5 of the Council of Europe’s Convention
for the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Being with regard
to the Application of biology and Medicine: Convention on Human Rights and
Biomedicine provides that “an intervention in the health field may only be
carried out after the person concerned has given free and informed consent to
it” (Council of Europe 1997). Article 5(b) of UNESCO’s Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights provides
that free and informed consent shall be obtained prior to medical research or
treatment or diagnosis affecting an individual’s genome (UNESCO 1997). [2] John K. Davis is
right to argue that substantive consent cannot be equated with forgiveness, but
this is simply because talk about subsequent consent has no meaning (Davis
2004, 287-88). At best we can forgive or approve after the fact. [3] I am indebted to Fritz Allhoff for his helpful comments on a previous draft. |