A peer-reviewed electronic journal published by the Institute for Ethics and
Emerging Technologies

ISSN 1541-0099

21(1) – January 2010

 

The Overhuman in the Transhuman

 

Max More

 

Strategic philosopher, The Proactionary Project

 

max@maxmore.com

 

Journal of Evolution and Technology  -  Vol. 21  Issue 1 – January 2010 - pgs 1-4
 http://jetpress.org/more.htm

 

Abstract

 

Stefan Sorgner (2009) says that on becoming familiar with transhumanism, he Òimmediately thought that there were many fundamental similarities between transhumanism and NietzscheÕs philosophy, especially concerning the concept of the posthuman and that of NietzscheÕs overhuman.Ó In contrast to Bostrom (2005), Sorgner sees significant and fundamental similarities between the posthuman and the overhuman. (I will adopt his use of ÒoverhumanÓ in place of ÒovermanÓ or †bermensch.) This overall view seems to me highly plausible. I agree with most of SorgnerÕs comments in this respect. My intent is to give further support to the conceptual parallels. In addition, I argue that these are not merely parallels: transhumanist ideas were directly influenced by Nietzsche.

 

Introduction

 

Should transhumanists look upon Friedrich NietzscheÕs thought as an embarrassment just as Nietzsche suggested the ape was to man? Is there an abyss between his Òphilosophy with a hammerÓ and the philosophy of transhumanism? Stefan Sorgner (2009) says that on becoming familiar with transhumanism, he Òimmediately thought that there were many fundamental similarities between transhumanism and NietzscheÕs philosophy, especially concerning the concept of the posthuman and that of NietzscheÕs overhuman.Ó In contrast to Bostrom (2005), Sorgner sees significant and fundamental similarities between the posthuman and the overhuman. (I will adopt his use of ÒoverhumanÓ in place of ÒovermanÓ or bermensch.) This overall view seems to me highly plausible. I agree with most of SorgnerÕs comments in this respect. My intent is to give further support to the conceptual parallels. In addition, I argue that these are not merely parallels: transhumanist ideas were directly influenced by Nietzsche.

 

First, it is necessary to note that an enormous range of ideas can be found in NietzscheÕs writing, some of which – especially comparing different periods of his work – may be inconsistent. Although there are clear parallels between NietzscheÕs thinking and some core transhumanist ideas, the latter are inspired very selectively by the former. Perhaps the most salient example of a Nietzschean idea alien to transhumanism is his Òeternal recurrence.Ó Nietzsche thought this idea inseparable from that of the overman (or overhuman).

 

Many scholars have been puzzled at this connection and have often rejected eternal recurrence. NietzscheÕs attachment to the concept probably results from his seeing it as the ultimate affirmation of the real world as against the Christian (and Platonic) denial of the primacy of the actual, physical reality. Not only is eternal recurrence a bizarre piece of metaphysics in itself, it was part of NietzscheÕs denial of the idea of progress. Both for its inherent implausibility and for its opposition to progress, this concept cannot be reconciled with transhumanism. Nevertheless, several other concepts can be so reconciled. As a strong opponent of philosophical systems, Nietzsche could hardly object to transhumanismÕs picking and choosing from among his thoughts.

 

Direct influence

 

SorgnerÕs essay establishes parallels between transhumanism and NietzscheÕs thought, but does not address the question of whether transhumanist ideas were directly influenced by Nietzsche. I can state with complete confidence that such an influence does indeed exist. I know that because his ideas influenced my own thinking. That thinking led to my introduction of the term ÒtranshumanismÓ (only later did I discover HuxleyÕs prior use of the term), to the publication of my essay, ÒTranshumanism: Towards a Futurist PhilosophyÓ (More 1990), and to my original transhumanist statement, ÒThe Extropian PrinciplesÓ (later ÒThe Principles of ExtropyÓ, More 1990b). While these essays are far from the only sources of contemporary transhumanism, these seminal writings have been influential. Since they were themselves influenced by some of NietzscheÕs core ideas, the direct connection between transhumanism and Nietzsche is established.

 

In ÒTranshumanism: Towards a Futurist Philosophy,Ó for instance, I wrote that ÒThe religionist has no answer to the extropic challenge put by NietzscheÕs Zarathustra: ÔI teach you the overman. Man is something that is to be overcome. What have you done to overcome him?ÕÓ Sorgner notes, ÒThe overhuman represents the meaning of the earth. The overhuman is supposed to represent the meaning-giving concept within NietzscheÕs worldview which is supposed to replace the basically Christian worldview.Ó He also states that ÒNietzsche upheld that the concept of the overhuman is the meaning of the earth. I think that the relevance of the posthuman can only be fully appreciated if one acknowledges that its ultimate foundation is that it gives meaning to scientifically minded people.Ó This again agrees closely with my ÒTranshumanismÓ essay in which I wrote: ÒI agree with Nietzsche (in The Will to Power) that nihilism is only a transitional stage resulting from the breakdown of an erroneous interpretation of the world. We now have plenty of resources to leave nihilism behind, affirming a positive (but continually evolving) value-perspective.Ó

 

Critical rationalism

 

Reflecting its humanist and Enlightenment roots, transhumanism places an extremely high value on rationality. Especially popular among transhumanists is critical rationalism. This form of rationalism differs from the foundationalist certitude of Descartes. In its most consistent form it becomes pancritical rationalism (Bartley 1984). As Sorgner points out, Nietzsche, too, had an immense respect for critical thinking and valued scientific inquiry highly.

 

In my 1994 talk on pancritical rationalism at the first Extropy Institute conference (More 1994), I started by citing NietzscheÕs statement: ÒA very popular error: having the courage of oneÕs convictions; rather it is a matter of having the courage for an attack on oneÕs convictions!Ó I might just as easily have cited another passage: ÒConvictions are more dangerous foes of truth than lies.Ó Or the passage from The Gay Science (Nietzsche 1882): ÒNot to question, not to tremble with the craving and joy of questioning É that is what I feel to be contemptible, and this feeling is the first thing I seek in everyone: some foolishness persuades me ever and again that every human being has this feeling, as a human being. It is my kind of injustice.Ó Although Nietzsche is not essential to critical rationalism, he does provide inspiration for what might otherwise seem a dry epistemology.

 

Self-Transformation

 

One of the core transhumanist principles of extropy has been that of Self-Transformation. In a later version of the Principles, this was complemented by the principle of Self-Direction. Both of these are highly compatible with NietzscheÕs thinking. They are also influenced by his work, along with that of many other thinkers. Most centrally, I would point to ZarathustraÕs declaration (Nietzsche 1885): ÒAnd life itself confided this secret to me: ÔBehold,Õ it said, ÔI am that which must always overcome itself.ÕÓ

 

From both the individual and species perspective, the concept of self-overcoming resonates strongly with extropic, transhumanist ideals and goals. Although Nietzsche had little to say about technology as a means of self-overcoming, neither did he rule it out. And, as a champion of what he saw as a coming age of science, it is not difficult to see technology as part of the process of self-overcoming, so long as it is integrated firmly with will and self-assertion. Self-assertion in this case, of course, being not assertion of an existing self to preserve itself, but a striving to Òbecome who you areÓ. New technologies allow us new means of becoming who we are – another step toward posthuman ideals – and new ways of Ògiving styleÓ to our character. As Nietzsche put it: Òa great and rare art!Ó

 

Utilitarianism, slave-morality, and heroic transhumanism

 

The sole reason Bostrom (2005) gives for saying that transhumanism has merely Òsome surface-level similarities with the Nietzschean visionÓ is that transhumanism – thanks to its Enlightenment roots – has an emphasis on individual liberties and a Òconcern for the welfare of all humans (and other sentient beings).Ó Bostrom is correct about this emphasis, as reflected, for instance, in the principle of Self-Direction in the Principles of Extropy. Bostrom concludes that transhumanism therefore Òprobably has as much or more in common with NietzscheÕs contemporary J.S. Mill, the English liberal thinker and utilitarian.Ó

 

Nietzsche famously had nothing positive to say about the utilitarians. When he mentioned them, it was to say something caustically critical, such as: ÒMan does not strive for pleasure; only the Englishman doesÓ (Nietzsche 1889). Should we infer from NietzscheÕs distaste for the slave-morality of utilitarianism (which turns every moral agent into a slave yoked to the task of maximizing the greatest good of the greatest number) that transhumanism has little in common with NietzscheÕs thinking? I think not.

 

What we can infer is that differing variants of transhumanism are possible. Certainly there is no inconsistency between transhumanism and a utilitarian morality. But neither is there any inconsistency between transhumanism and a more Nietzschean view of morality. While Nietzsche viewed morality as essentially perspectival, we can easily enough fit him loosely within the virtue ethics approach classically represented by Aristotle. Yes, transhumanism can be sanitized and made safe so that it fits comfortably with utilitarian thinking. Or we can take seriously NietzscheÕs determination to undertake a Òrevaluation of all values.Ó

 

This not need imply any kind of illiberal social or political system. It may simply lead to a version of transhumanism that champions the self-overcoming of the individual without an obligation to Òthe masses.Ó Many sound pragmatic reasons exist for each of us to want to uplift everyone – at least for those of us who reject the idea of society and economy as a zero-sum game. Pragmatic considerations are not the only reason a Nietzschean transhumanist may have for benevolence of this kind. Unlike a utilitarian transhumanist who must regard uplifting others as an obligation, a Nietzschean transhumanist would look upon the prospect of uplifting the masses as an expression of overflowing personal power or well-being or health.

 

Neither a utilitarian nor a Nietzschean transhumanism can plausibly claim to be the true transhumanism. Both share the central elements of the radical transhumanist worldview. My goal has not been to show that transhumanism must be Nietzschean. It has been to show that central elements of NietzscheÕs philosophy are not only compatible with transhumanism, but have historically had a considerable direct influence on major strands of this philosophy of life.

 

 

References

 

Bartley, W. W. III. 1984. The retreat to commitment. 2nd edition; Chicago: Open Court.

 

Bostrom, N. 2005. A history of transhumanist thought. Journal of Evolution and Technology 14 (1).

 

Kaufmann, W. A. 1974. Nietzsche: Philosopher, psychologist, antichrist. 4th edition; Princeton: Princeton University Press.

 

More, M. 1990, revised 1996. Transhumanism: Towards a futurist philosophy. Extropy 6.

<http://www.maxmore.com/transhum.htm>

 

More, M. (1990b revised 2003). The principles of extropy, version 3.11. Extropy 5.5 (1990 version).

<http://www.extropy.org/principles.htm>

 

More, M. 1994. Pancritical rationalism: An extropic metacontext for memetic progress. Proceedings of the Extro-1 Conference, Extropy Institute.

 

Nietzsche, F. 1889. Twilight of the idols. (Available in various editions.)

 

Nietzsche, F. 1885. Zarathustra II 12. (Available in various editions.)

 

Nietzsche, F. 1882. The gay science. (Available in various editions.)

 

Sorgner, S. L. 2009. Nietzsche, the overhuman, and transhumanism. Journal of Evolution and Technology 20(1): 29-42.